§ Idealism and Materialism
§ The Illusions of German Ideology
¶As we hear from German ideologists, Germany has in the last few years
gone through an unparalleled revolution. The decomposition of the
Hegelian philosophy, which began with Strauss, has developed into a
universal ferment into which all the powers of the past
are
swept. In the general chaos mighty empires have arisen only to meet with
immediate doom, heroes have emerged momentarily only to be hurled back
into obscurity by bolder and stronger rivals. It was a revolution beside
which the French Revolution was child’s play, a world struggle beside
which the struggles of the Diadochi [successors of Alexander the Great]
appear insignificant. Principles ousted one another, heroes of the mind
overthrew each other with unheard-of rapidity, and in the three years
1842-45 more of the past was swept away in Germany than at other times
in three centuries.
¶All this is supposed to have taken place in the realm of pure thought.
¶Certainly it is an interesting event we are dealing with: the putrescence of the absolute spirit. When the last spark of its life had failed, the various components of this caput mortuum began to decompose, entered into new combinations and formed new substances. The industrialists of philosophy, who till then had lived on the exploitation of the absolute spirit, now seized upon the new combinations. Each with all possible zeal set about retailing his apportioned share. This naturally gave rise to competition, which, to start with, was carried on in moderately staid bourgeois fashion. Later when the German market was glutted, and the commodity in spite of all efforts found no response in the world market, the business was spoiled in the usual German manner by fabricated and fictitious production, deterioration in quality, adulteration of the raw materials, falsification of labels, fictitious purchases, bill-jobbing and a credit system devoid of any real basis. The competition turned into a bitter struggle, which is now being extolled and interpreted to us as a revolution of world significance, the begetter of the most prodigious results and achievements.
¶If we wish to rate at its true value this philosophic charlatanry, which awakens even in the breast of the honest German citizen a glow of national pride, if we wish to bring out clearly the pettiness, the parochial narrowness of this whole Young-Hegelian movement and in particular the tragicomic contrast between the illusions of these heroes about their achievements and the actual achievements themselves, we must look at the whole spectacle from a standpoint beyond the frontiers of Germany.
§ Ideology in General, German Ideology in Particular
¶German criticism has, right up to its latest efforts, never quitted
the realm of philosophy. Far from examining its general philosophic
premises, the whole body of its inquiries has actually sprung from the
soil of a definite philosophical system, that of Hegel. Not only in
their answers but in their very questions there was a mystification.
This dependence on Hegel is the reason why not one of these modern
critics has even attempted a comprehensive criticism of the Hegelian
system, however much each professes to have advanced beyond Hegel. Their
polemics against Hegel and against one another are confined to this –
each extracts one side of the Hegelian system and turns this against the
whole system as well as against the sides extracted by the others. To
begin with they extracted pure unfalsified Hegelian categories such as
substance
and self-consciousness,
later they desecrated
these categories with more secular names such as species the
Unique,
Man,
etc.
¶The entire body of German philosophical criticism from Strauss to
Stirner is confined to criticism of religious conceptions. The critics
started from real religion and actual theology. What religious
consciousness and a religious conception really meant was determined
variously as they went along. Their advance consisted in subsuming the
allegedly dominant metaphysical, political, juridical, moral and other
conceptions under the class of religious or theological conceptions; and
similarly in pronouncing political, juridical, moral consciousness as
religious or theological, and the political, juridical, moral man –
man
in the last resort – as religious. The dominance of religion
was taken for granted. Gradually every dominant relationship was
pronounced a religious relationship and transformed into a cult, a cult
of law, a cult of the State, etc. On all sides it was only a question of
dogmas and belief in dogmas. The world was sanctified to an
ever-increasing extent till at last our venerable Saint Max was able to
canonise it en bloc and thus dispose of it once for all.
¶The Old Hegelians had comprehended everything as soon as it was reduced to an Hegelian logical category. The Young Hegelians criticised everything by attributing to it religious conceptions or by pronouncing it a theological matter. The Young Hegelians are in agreement with the Old Hegelians in their belief in the rule of religion, of concepts, of a universal principle in the existing world. Only, the one party attacks this dominion as usurpation, while the other extols it as legitimate.
¶Since the Young Hegelians consider conceptions, thoughts, ideas, in
fact all the products of consciousness, to which they attribute an
independent existence, as the real chains of men (just as the Old
Hegelians declared them the true bonds of human society) it is evident
that the Young Hegelians have to fight only against these illusions of
consciousness. Since, according to their fantasy, the relationships of
men, all their doings, their chains and their limitations are products
of their consciousness, the Young Hegelians logically put to men the
moral postulate of exchanging their present consciousness for human,
critical or egoistic consciousness, and thus of removing their
limitations. This demand to change consciousness amounts to a demand to
interpret reality in another way, i.e. to recognise it by means of
another interpretation. The Young-Hegelian ideologists, in spite of
their allegedly world-shattering
statements, are the staunchest
conservatives. The most recent of them have found the correct expression
for their activity when they declare they are only fighting against
phrases.
They forget, however, that to these phrases they
themselves are only opposing other phrases, and that they are in no way
combating the real existing world when they are merely combating the
phrases of this world. The only results which this philosophic criticism
could achieve were a few (and at that thoroughly one-sided) elucidations
of Christianity from the point of view of religious history; all the
rest of their assertions are only further embellishments of their claim
to have furnished, in these unimportant elucidations, discoveries of
universal importance.
¶It has not occurred to any one of these philosophers to inquire into the connection of German philosophy with German reality, the relation of their criticism to their own material surroundings.
§ First Premises of Materialist Method
¶The premises from which we begin are not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real premises from which abstraction can only be made in the imagination. They are the real individuals, their activity and the material conditions under which they live, both those which they find already existing and those produced by their activity. These premises can thus be verified in a purely empirical way.
¶The first premise of all human history is, of course, the existence of living human individuals. Thus the first fact to be established is the physical organisation of these individuals and their consequent relation to the rest of nature. Of course, we cannot here go either into the actual physical nature of man, or into the natural conditions in which man finds himself – geological, hydrographical, climatic and so on. The writing of history must always set out from these natural bases and their modification in the course of history through the action of men.
¶Men can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by religion or anything else you like. They themselves begin to distinguish themselves from animals as soon as they begin to produce their means of subsistence, a step which is conditioned by their physical organisation. By producing their means of subsistence men are indirectly producing their actual material life.
¶The way in which men produce their means of subsistence depends first of all on the nature of the actual means of subsistence they find in existence and have to reproduce. This mode of production must not be considered simply as being the production of the physical existence of the individuals. Rather it is a definite form of activity of these individuals, a definite form of expressing their life, a definite mode of life on their part. As individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore, coincides with their production, both with what they produce and with how they produce. The nature of individuals thus depends on the material conditions determining their production.
¶This production only makes its appearance with the increase of population. In its turn this presupposes the intercourse [Verkehr] of individuals with one another. The form of this intercourse is again determined by production.
Production and Intercourse Division of Labour and Forms of Property – Tribal, Ancient, Feudal
¶The relations of different nations among themselves depend upon the extent to which each has developed its productive forces, the division of labour and internal intercourse. This statement is generally recognised. But not only the relation of one nation to others, but also the whole internal structure of the nation itself depends on the stage of development reached by its production and its internal and external intercourse. How far the productive forces of a nation are developed is shown most manifestly by the degree to which the division of labour has been carried. Each new productive force, insofar as it is not merely a quantitative extension of productive forces already known (for instance the bringing into cultivation of fresh land), causes a further development of the division of labour.
¶The division of labour inside a nation leads at first to the separation of industrial and commercial from agricultural labour, and hence to the separation of town and country and to the conflict of their interests. Its further development leads to the separation of commercial from industrial labour. At the same time through the division of labour inside these various branches there develop various divisions among the individuals co-operating in definite kinds of labour. The relative position of these individual groups is determined by the methods employed in agriculture, industry and commerce (patriarchalism, slavery, estates, classes). These same conditions are to be seen (given a more developed intercourse) in the relations of different nations to one another.
¶The various stages of development in the division of labour are just so many different forms of ownership, i.e. the existing stage in the division of labour determines also the relations of individuals to one another with reference to the material, instrument, and product of labour.
¶The first form of ownership is tribal [Stammeigentum] ownership. It corresponds to the undeveloped stage of production, at which a people lives by hunting and fishing, by the rearing of beasts or, in the highest stage, agriculture. In the latter case it presupposes a great mass of uncultivated stretches of land. The division of labour is at this stage still very elementary and is confined to a further extension of the natural division of labour existing in the family. The social structure is, therefore, limited to an extension of the family; patriarchal family chieftains, below them the members of the tribe, finally slaves. The slavery latent in the family only develops gradually with the increase of population, the growth of wants, and with the extension of external relations, both of war and of barter.
¶The second form is the ancient communal and State ownership which proceeds especially from the union of several tribes into a city by agreement or by conquest, and which is still accompanied by slavery. Beside communal ownership we already find movable, and later also immovable, private property developing, but as an abnormal form subordinate to communal ownership. The citizens hold power over their labouring slaves only in their community, and on this account alone, therefore, they are bound to the form of communal ownership. It is the communal private property which compels the active citizens to remain in this spontaneously derived form of association over against their slaves. For this reason the whole structure of society based on this communal ownership, and with it the power of the people, decays in the same measure as, in particular, immovable private property evolves. The division of labour is already more developed. We already find the antagonism of town and country; later the antagonism between those states which represent town interests and those which represent country interests, and inside the towns themselves the antagonism between industry and maritime commerce. The class relation between citizens and slaves is now completely developed.
¶With the development of private property, we find here for the first time the same conditions which we shall find again, only on a more extensive scale, with modern private property. On the one hand, the concentration of private property, which began very early in Rome (as the Licinian agrarian law proves) and proceeded very rapidly from the time of the civil wars and especially under the Emperors; on the other hand, coupled with this, the transformation of the plebeian small peasantry into a proletariat, which, however, owing to its intermediate position between propertied citizens and slaves, never achieved an independent development.
¶The third form of ownership is feudal or estate property. If antiquity started out from the town and its little territory, the Middle Ages started out from the country. This different starting-point was determined by the sparseness of the population at that time, which was scattered over a large area and which received no large increase from the conquerors. In contrast to Greece and Rome, feudal development at the outset, therefore, extends over a much wider territory, prepared by the Roman conquests and the spread of agriculture at first associated with it. The last centuries of the declining Roman Empire and its conquest by the barbarians destroyed a number of productive forces; agriculture had declined, industry had decayed for want of a market, trade had died out or been violently suspended, the rural and urban population had decreased. From these conditions and the mode of organisation of the conquest determined by them, feudal property developed under the influence of the Germanic military constitution. Like tribal and communal ownership, it is based again on a community; but the directly producing class standing over against it is not, as in the case of the ancient community, the slaves, but the enserfed small peasantry. As soon as feudalism is fully developed, there also arises antagonism to the towns. The hierarchical structure of land ownership, and the armed bodies of retainers associated with it, gave the nobility power over the serfs. This feudal organisation was, just as much as the ancient communal ownership, an association against a subjected producing class; but the form of association and the relation to the direct producers were different because of the different conditions of production.
¶This feudal system of land ownership had its counterpart in the towns in the shape of corporative property, the feudal organisation of trades. Here property consisted chiefly in the labour of each individual person. The necessity for association against the organised robber-nobility, the need for communal covered markets in an age when the industrialist was at the same time a merchant, the growing competition of the escaped serfs swarming into the rising towns, the feudal structure of the whole country: these combined to bring about the guilds. The gradually accumulated small capital of individual craftsmen and their stable numbers, as against the growing population, evolved the relation of journeyman and apprentice, which brought into being in the towns a hierarchy similar to that in the country.
¶Thus the chief form of property during the feudal epoch consisted on the one hand of landed property with serf labour chained to it, and on the other of the labour of the individual with small capital commanding the labour of journeymen. The organisation of both was determined by the restricted conditions of production – the small-scale and primitive cultivation of the land, and the craft type of industry. There was little division of labour in the heyday of feudalism. Each country bore in itself the antithesis of town and country; the division into estates was certainly strongly marked; but apart from the differentiation of princes, nobility, clergy and peasants in the country, and masters, journeymen, apprentices and soon also the rabble of casual labourers in the towns, no division of importance took place. In agriculture it was rendered difficult by the strip-system, beside which the cottage industry of the peasants themselves emerged. In industry there was no division of labour at all in the individual trades themselves, and very little between them. The separation of industry and commerce was found already in existence in older towns; in the newer it only developed later, when the towns entered into mutual relations.
¶The grouping of larger territories into feudal kingdoms was a necessity for the landed nobility as for the towns. The organisation of the ruling class, the nobility, had, therefore, everywhere a monarch at its head.
The Essence of the Materialist Conception of History. Social Being and Social Consciousness
¶The fact is, therefore, that definite individuals who are productively active in a definite way enter into these definite social and political relations. Empirical observation must in each separate instance bring out empirically, and without any mystification and speculation, the connection of the social and political structure with production. The social structure and the State are continually evolving out of the life-process of definite individuals, but of individuals, not as they may appear in their own or other people’s imagination, but as they really are; i.e. as they operate, produce materially, and hence as they work under definite material limits, presuppositions and conditions independent of their will.
¶The production of ideas, of conceptions, of consciousness, is at first directly interwoven with the material activity and the material intercourse of men, the language of real life. Conceiving, thinking, the mental intercourse of men, appear at this stage as the direct efflux of their material behaviour. The same applies to mental production as expressed in the language of politics, laws, morality, religion, metaphysics, etc., of a people. Men are the producers of their conceptions, ideas, etc. – real, active men, as they are conditioned by a definite development of their productive forces and of the intercourse corresponding to these, up to its furthest forms. Consciousness can never be anything else than conscious existence, and the existence of men is their actual life-process. If in all ideology men and their circumstances appear upside-down as in a camera obscura, this phenomenon arises just as much from their historical life-process as the inversion of objects on the retina does from their physical life-process.
¶In direct contrast to German philosophy which descends from heaven to earth, here we ascend from earth to heaven. That is to say, we do not set out from what men say, imagine, conceive, nor from men as narrated, thought of, imagined, conceived, in order to arrive at men in the flesh. We set out from real, active men, and on the basis of their real life-process we demonstrate the development of the ideological reflexes and echoes of this life-process. The phantoms formed in the human brain are also, necessarily, sublimates of their material life-process, which is empirically verifiable and bound to material premises. Morality, religion, metaphysics, all the rest of ideology and their corresponding forms of consciousness, thus no longer retain the semblance of independence. They have no history, no development; but men, developing their material production and their material intercourse, alter, along with this their real existence, their thinking and the products of their thinking. Life is not determined by consciousness, but consciousness by life. In the first method of approach the starting-point is consciousness taken as the living individual; in the second method, which conforms to real life, it is the real living individuals themselves, and consciousness is considered solely as their consciousness.
¶This method of approach is not devoid of premises. It starts out from the real premises and does not abandon them for a moment. Its premises are men, not in any fantastic isolation and rigidity, but in their actual, empirically perceptible process of development under definite conditions. As soon as this active life-process is described, history ceases to be a collection of dead facts as it is with the empiricists (themselves still abstract), or an imagined activity of imagined subjects, as with the idealists.
¶Where speculation ends – in real life – there real, positive science begins: the representation of the practical activity, of the practical process of development of men. Empty talk about consciousness ceases, and real knowledge has to take its place. When reality is depicted, philosophy as an independent branch of knowledge loses its medium of existence. At the best its place can only be taken by a summing-up of the most general results, abstractions which arise from the observation of the historical development of men. Viewed apart from real history, these abstractions have in themselves no value whatsoever. They can only serve to facilitate the arrangement of historical material, to indicate the sequence of its separate strata. But they by no means afford a recipe or schema, as does philosophy, for neatly trimming the epochs of history. On the contrary, our difficulties begin only when we set about the observation and the arrangement – the real depiction – of our historical material, whether of a past epoch or of the present. The removal of these difficulties is governed by premises which it is quite impossible to state here, but which only the study of the actual life-process and the activity of the individuals of each epoch will make evident. We shall select here some of these abstractions, which we use in contradistinction to the ideologists, and shall illustrate them by historical examples.
§ History: Fundamental Conditions
¶Since we are dealing with the Germans, who are devoid of premises, we
must begin by stating the first premise of all human existence and,
therefore, of all history, the premise, namely, that men must be in a
position to live in order to be able to make history.
But life
involves before everything else eating and drinking, a habitation,
clothing and many other things. The first historical act is thus the
production of the means to satisfy these needs, the production of
material life itself. And indeed this is an historical act, a
fundamental condition of all history, which today, as thousands of years
ago, must daily and hourly be fulfilled merely in order to sustain human
life. Even when the sensuous world is reduced to a minimum, to a stick
as with Saint Bruno [Bauer], it presupposes the action of producing the
stick. Therefore in any interpretation of history one has first of all
to observe this fundamental fact in all its significance and all its
implications and to accord it its due importance. It is well known that
the Germans have never done this, and they have never, therefore, had an
earthly basis for history and consequently never an historian. The
French and the English, even if they have conceived the relation of this
fact with so-called history only in an extremely one-sided fashion,
particularly as long as they remained in the toils of political
ideology, have nevertheless made the first attempts to give the writing
of history a materialistic basis by being the first to write histories
of civil society, of commerce and industry.
¶The second point is that the satisfaction of the first need (the
action of satisfying, and the instrument of satisfaction which has been
acquired) leads to new needs; and this production of new needs is the
first historical act. Here we recognise immediately the spiritual
ancestry of the great historical wisdom of the Germans who, when they
run out of positive material and when they can serve up neither
theological nor political nor literary rubbish, assert that this is not
history at all, but the prehistoric era.
They do not, however,
enlighten us as to how we proceed from this nonsensical
prehistory
to history proper; although, on the other hand, in
their historical speculation they seize upon this prehistory
with
especial eagerness because they imagine themselves safe there from
interference on the part of crude facts,
and, at the same time,
because there they can give full rein to their speculative impulse and
set up and knock down hypotheses by the thousand.
¶The third circumstance which, from the very outset, enters into
historical development, is that men, who daily remake their own life,
begin to make other men, to propagate their kind: the relation between
man and woman, parents and children, the family. The family, which to
begin with is the only social relationship, becomes later, when
increased needs create new social relations and the increased population
new needs, a subordinate one (except in Germany), and must then be
treated and analysed according to the existing empirical data, not
according to the concept of the family,
as is the custom in
Germany.1 These three aspects of social
activity are not of course to be taken as three different stages, but
just as three aspects or, to make it clear to the Germans, three
moments,
which have existed simultaneously since the dawn of
history and the first men, and which still assert themselves in history
today.
¶The production of life, both of one’s own in labour and of fresh life
in procreation, now appears as a double relationship: on the one hand as
a natural, on the other as a social relationship. By social we
understand the co-operation of several individuals, no matter under what
conditions, in what manner and to what end. It follows from this that a
certain mode of production, or industrial stage, is always combined with
a certain mode of co-operation, or social stage, and this mode of
co-operation is itself a productive force.
Further, that the
multitude of productive forces accessible to men determines the nature
of society, hence, that the history of humanity
must always be
studied and treated in relation to the history of industry and exchange.
But it is also clear how in Germany it is impossible to write this sort
of history, because the Germans lack not only the necessary power of
comprehension and the material but also the evidence of their
senses,
for across the Rhine you cannot have any experience of these
things since history has stopped happening. Thus it is quite obvious
from the start that there exists a materialistic connection of men with
one another, which is determined by their needs and their mode of
production, and which is as old as men themselves. This connection is
ever taking on new forms, and thus presents a history
independently of the existence of any political or religious nonsense
which in addition may hold men together.
¶Only now, after having considered four moments, four aspects of the
primary historical relationships, do we find that man also possesses
consciousness,
but, even so, not inherent, not pure
consciousness. From the start the spirit
is afflicted with the
curse of being burdened
with matter, which here makes its
appearance in the form of agitated layers of air, sounds, in short, of
language. Language is as old as consciousness, language is practical
consciousness that exists also for other men, and for that reason alone
it really exists for me personally as well; language, like
consciousness, only arises from the need, the necessity, of intercourse
with other men. Where there exists a relationship, it exists for me: the
animal does not enter into relations
with anything, it does not
enter into any relation at all. For the animal, its relation to others
does not exist as a relation. Consciousness is, therefore, from the very
beginning a social product, and remains so as long as men exist at all.
Consciousness is at first, of course, merely consciousness concerning
the immediate sensuous environment and consciousness of the limited
connection with other persons and things outside the individual who is
growing self-conscious. At the same time it is consciousness of nature,
which first appears to men as a completely alien, all-powerful and
unassailable force, with which men’s relations are purely animal and by
which they are overawed like beasts; it is thus a purely animal
consciousness of nature (natural religion) just because nature is as yet
hardly modified historically. (We see here immediately: this natural
religion or this particular relation of men to nature is determined by
the form of society and vice versa. Here, as everywhere, the identity of
nature and man appears in such a way that the restricted relation of men
to nature determines their restricted relation to one another, and their
restricted relation to one another determines men’s restricted relation
to nature.) On the other hand, man’s consciousness of the necessity of
associating with the individuals around him is the beginning of the
consciousness that he is living in society at all. This beginning is as
animal as social life itself at this stage. It is mere
herd-consciousness, and at this point man is only distinguished from
sheep by the fact that with him consciousness takes the place of
instinct or that his instinct is a conscious one. This sheep-like or
tribal consciousness receives its further development and extension
through increased productivity, the increase of needs, and, what is
fundamental to both of these, the increase of population. With these
there develops the division of labour, which was originally nothing but
the division of labour in the sexual act, then that division of labour
which develops spontaneously or naturally
by virtue of natural
predisposition (e.g. physical strength), needs, accidents, etc. etc.
Division of labour only becomes truly such from the moment when a
division of material and mental labour appears. (The first form of
ideologists, priests, is concurrent.) From this moment onwards
consciousness can really flatter itself that it is something other than
consciousness of existing practice, that it really represents something
without representing something real; from now on consciousness is in a
position to emancipate itself from the world and to proceed to the
formation of pure
theory, theology, philosophy, ethics, etc. But
even if this theory, theology, philosophy, ethics, etc. comes into
contradiction with the existing relations, this can only occur because
existing social relations have come into contradiction with existing
forces of production; this, moreover, can also occur in a particular
national sphere of relations through the appearance of the
contradiction, not within the national orbit, but between this national
consciousness and the practice of other nations, i.e. between the
national and the general consciousness of a nation (as we see it now in
Germany).
¶Moreover, it is quite immaterial what consciousness starts to do on
its own: out of all such muck we get only the one inference that these
three moments, the forces of production, the state of society, and
consciousness, can and must come into contradiction with one another,
because the division of labour implies the possibility, nay the fact
that intellectual and material activity – enjoyment and labour,
production and consumption – devolve on different individuals, and that
the only possibility of their not coming into contradiction lies in the
negation in its turn of the division of labour. It is self-evident,
moreover, that spectres,
bonds,
the higher being,
concept,
scruple,
are merely the idealistic, spiritual
expression, the conception apparently of the isolated individual, the
image of very empirical fetters and limitations, within which the mode
of production of life and the form of intercourse coupled with it
move.
§ Private Property and Communism
¶With the division of labour, in which all these contradictions are implicit, and which in its turn is based on the natural division of labour in the family and the separation of society into individual families opposed to one another, is given simultaneously the distribution, and indeed the unequal distribution, both quantitative and qualitative, of labour and its products, hence property: the nucleus, the first form, of which lies in the family, where wife and children are the slaves of the husband. This latent slavery in the family, though still very crude, is the first property, but even at this early stage it corresponds perfectly to the definition of modern economists who call it the power of disposing of the labour-power of others. Division of labour and private property are, moreover, identical expressions: in the one the same thing is affirmed with reference to activity as is affirmed in the other with reference to the product of the activity.
¶Further, the division of labour implies the contradiction between the
interest of the separate individual or the individual family and the
communal interest of all individuals who have intercourse with one
another. And indeed, this communal interest does not exist merely in the
imagination, as the general interest,
but first of all in
reality, as the mutual interdependence of the individuals among whom the
labour is divided. And finally, the division of labour offers us the
first example of how, as long as man remains in natural society, that
is, as long as a cleavage exists between the particular and the common
interest, as long, therefore, as activity is not voluntarily, but
naturally, divided, man’s own deed becomes an alien power opposed to
him, which enslaves him instead of being controlled by him. For as soon
as the distribution of labour comes into being, each man has a
particular, exclusive sphere of activity, which is forced upon him and
from which he cannot escape. He is a hunter, a fisherman, a herdsman, or
a critical critic, and must remain so if he does not want to lose his
means of livelihood; while in communist society, where nobody has one
exclusive sphere of activity but each can become accomplished in any
branch he wishes, society regulates the general production and thus
makes it possible for me to do one thing today and another tomorrow, to
hunt in the morning, fish in the afternoon, rear cattle in the evening,
criticise after dinner, just as I have a mind, without ever becoming
hunter, fisherman, herdsman or critic. This fixation of social activity,
this consolidation of what we ourselves produce into an objective power
above us, growing out of our control, thwarting our expectations,
bringing to naught our calculations, is one of the chief factors in
historical development up till now.2
¶The social power, i.e., the multiplied productive force, which arises through the co-operation of different individuals as it is determined by the division of labour, appears to these individuals, since their co-operation is not voluntary but has come about naturally, not as their own united power, but as an alien force existing outside them, of the origin and goal of which they are ignorant, which they thus cannot control, which on the contrary passes through a peculiar series of phases and stages independent of the will and the action of man, nay even being the prime governor of these.
¶How otherwise could, for instance, property have had a history at all, have taken on different forms, and landed property, for example, according to the different premises given, have proceeded in France from parcellation to centralisation in the hands of a few, in England from centralisation in the hands of a few to parcellation, as is actually the case today? Or how does it happen that trade, which after all is nothing more than the exchange of products of various individuals and countries, rules the whole world through the relation of supply and demand – a relation which, as an English economist says, hovers over the earth like the fate of the ancients, and with invisible hand allots fortune and misfortune to men, sets up empires and overthrows empires, causes nations to rise and to disappear – while with the abolition of the basis of private property, with the communistic regulation of production (and, implicit in this, the destruction of the alien relation between men and what they themselves produce), the power of the relation of supply and demand is dissolved into nothing, and men get exchange, production, the mode of their mutual relation, under their own control again?
§ History as a Continuous Process
¶In history up to the present it is certainly an empirical fact that
separate individuals have, with the broadening of their activity into
world-historical activity, become more and more enslaved under a power
alien to them (a pressure which they have conceived of as a dirty trick
on the part of the so-called universal spirit, etc.), a power which has
become more and more enormous and, in the last instance, turns out to be
the world market. But it is just as empirically established that, by the
overthrow of the existing state of society by the communist revolution
(of which more below) and the abolition of private property which is
identical with it, this power, which so baffles the German
theoreticians, will be dissolved; and that then the liberation of each
single individual will be accomplished in the measure in which history
becomes transformed into world history. From the above it is clear that
the real intellectual wealth of the individual depends entirely on the
wealth of his real connections. Only then will the separate individuals
be liberated from the various national and local barriers, be brought
into practical connection with the material and intellectual production
of the whole world and be put in a position to acquire the capacity to
enjoy this all-sided production of the whole earth (the creations of
man). All-round dependence, this natural form of the world-historical
co-operation of individuals, will be transformed by this communist
revolution into the control and conscious mastery of these powers,
which, born of the action of men on one another, have till now overawed
and governed men as powers completely alien to them. Now this view can
be expressed again in speculative-idealistic, i.e. fantastic, terms as
self-generation of the species
(society as the subject
),
and thereby the consecutive series of interrelated individuals connected
with each other can be conceived as a single individual, which
accomplishes the mystery of generating itself. It is clear here that
individuals certainly make one another, physically and mentally, but do
not make themselves.
Development of the Productive Forces as a Material Premise of Communism
¶This alienation
(to use a term which will be comprehensible to
the philosophers) can, of course, only be abolished given two practical
premises. For it to become an intolerable
power, i.e. a power
against which men make a revolution, it must necessarily have rendered
the great mass of humanity propertyless,
and produced, at the
same time, the contradiction of an existing world of wealth and culture,
both of which conditions presuppose a great increase in productive
power, a high degree of its development. And, on the other hand, this
development of productive forces (which itself implies the actual
empirical existence of men in their world-historical, instead of local,
being) is an absolutely necessary practical premise because without it
want is merely made general, and with destitution the struggle for
necessities and all the old filthy business would necessarily be
reproduced; and furthermore, because only with this universal
development of productive forces is a universal intercourse between men
established, which produces in all nations simultaneously the phenomenon
of the propertyless
mass (universal competition), makes each
nation dependent on the revolutions of the others, and finally has put
world-historical, empirically universal individuals in place of local
ones. Without this, (1) communism could only exist as a local event; (2)
the forces of intercourse themselves could not have developed as
universal, hence intolerable powers: they would have remained home-bred
conditions surrounded by superstition; and (3) each extension of
intercourse would abolish local communism. Empirically, communism is
only possible as the act of the dominant peoples all at once
and
simultaneously, which presupposes the universal development of
productive forces and the world intercourse bound up with communism.
Moreover, the mass of propertyless workers – the utterly precarious
position of labour – power on a mass scale cut off from capital or from
even a limited satisfaction and, therefore, no longer merely temporarily
deprived of work itself as a secure source of life – presupposes the
world market through competition. The proletariat can thus only exist
world-historically, just as communism, its activity, can only have a
world-historical
existence. World-historical existence of
individuals means existence of individuals which is directly linked up
with world history.
¶Communism is for us not a state of affairs which is to be established, an ideal to which reality [will] have to adjust itself. We call communism the real movement which abolishes the present state of things. The conditions of this movement result from the premises now in existence.
¶In the main we have so far considered only one aspect of human activity, the reshaping of nature by men. The other aspect, the reshaping of men by men … [Intercourse and productive power]
¶Origin of the state and the relation of the state to civil society. …
§ The Illusion of the Epoch
§ Civil Society and the Conception of History
¶The form of intercourse determined by the existing productive forces at all previous historical stages, and in its turn determining these, is civil society. The latter, as is clear from what we have said above, has as its premises and basis the simple family and the multiple, the so-called tribe, the more precise determinants of this society are enumerated in our remarks above. Already here we see how this civil society is the true source and theatre of all history, and how absurd is the conception of history held hitherto, which neglects the real relationships and confines itself to high-sounding dramas of princes and states.
¶Civil society embraces the whole material intercourse of individuals
within a definite stage of the development of productive forces. It
embraces the whole commercial and industrial life of a given stage and,
insofar, transcends the State and the nation, though, on the other hand
again, it must assert itself in its foreign relations as nationality,
and inwardly must organise itself as State. The word civil
society
[bürgerliche Gesellschaft] emerged in the eighteenth
century, when property relationships had already extricated themselves
from the ancient and medieval communal society. Civil society as such
only develops with the bourgeoisie; the social organisation evolving
directly out of production and commerce, which in all ages forms the
basis of the State and of the rest of the idealistic superstructure,
has, however, always been designated by the same name.
Conclusions from the Materialist Conception of History
¶History is nothing but the succession of the separate generations,
each of which exploits the materials, the capital funds, the productive
forces handed down to it by all preceding generations, and thus, on the
one hand, continues the traditional activity in completely changed
circumstances and, on the other, modifies the old circumstances with a
completely changed activity. This can be speculatively distorted so that
later history is made the goal of earlier history, e.g. the goal
ascribed to the discovery of America is to further the eruption of the
French Revolution. Thereby history receives its own special aims and
becomes a person rating with other persons
(to wit:
Self-Consciousness, Criticism, the Unique,
etc.), while what is
designated with the words destiny,
goal,
germ,
or
idea
of earlier history is nothing more than an abstraction
formed from later history, from the active influence which earlier
history exercises on later history.
¶The further the separate spheres, which interact on one another,
extend in the course of this development, the more the original
isolation of the separate nationalities is destroyed by the developed
mode of production and intercourse and the division of labour between
various nations naturally brought forth by these, the more history
becomes world history. Thus, for instance, if in England a machine is
invented, which deprives countless workers of bread in India and China,
and overturns the whole form of existence of these empires, this
invention becomes a world-historical fact. Or again, take the case of
sugar and coffee which have proved their world-historical importance in
the nineteenth century by the fact that the lack of these products,
occasioned by the Napoleonic Continental System, caused the Germans to
rise against Napoleon, and thus became the real basis of the glorious
Wars of liberation of 1813. From this it follows that this
transformation of history into world history is not indeed a mere
abstract act on the part of the self-consciousness,
the world
spirit, or of any other metaphysical spectre, but a quite material,
empirically verifiable act, an act the proof of which every individual
furnishes as he comes and goes, eats, drinks and clothes himself.
§ Summary of the Materialist Conception of History
¶This conception of history depends on our ability to expound the real
process of production, starting out from the material production of life
itself, and to comprehend the form of intercourse connected with this
and created by this mode of production (i.e. civil society in its
various stages), as the basis of all history; and to show it in its
action as State, to explain all the different theoretical products and
forms of consciousness, religion, philosophy, ethics, etc. etc. and
trace their origins and growth from that basis; by which means, of
course, the whole thing can be depicted in its totality (and therefore,
too, the reciprocal action of these various sides on one another). It
has not, like the idealistic view of history, in every period to look
for a category, but remains constantly on the real ground of history; it
does not explain practice from the idea but explains the formation of
ideas from material practice; and accordingly it comes to the conclusion
that all forms and products of consciousness cannot be dissolved by
mental criticism, by resolution into self-consciousness
or
transformation into apparitions,
spectres,
fancies,
etc. but only by the practical overthrow of the actual social relations
which gave rise to this idealistic humbug; that not criticism but
revolution is the driving force of history, also of religion, of
philosophy and all other types of theory. It shows that history does not
end by being resolved into self-consciousness as spirit of the
spirit,
but that in it at each stage there is found a material
result: a sum of productive forces, an historically created relation of
individuals to nature and to one another, which is handed down to each
generation from its predecessor; a mass of productive forces, capital
funds and conditions, which, on the one hand, is indeed modified by the
new generation, but also on the other prescribes for it its conditions
of life and gives it a definite development, a special character. It
shows that circumstances make men just as much as men make
circumstances.
¶This sum of productive forces, capital funds and social forms of
intercourse, which every individual and generation finds in existence as
something given, is the real basis of what the philosophers have
conceived as substance
and essence of man,
and what they
have deified and attacked; a real basis which is not in the least
disturbed, in its effect and influence on the development of men, by the
fact that these philosophers revolt against it as
self-consciousness
and the Unique.
These conditions of
life, which different generations find in existence, decide also whether
or not the periodically recurring revolutionary convulsion will be
strong enough to overthrow the basis of the entire existing system. And
if these material elements of a complete revolution are not present
(namely, on the one hand the existing productive forces, on the other
the formation of a revolutionary mass, which revolts not only against
separate conditions of society up till then, but against the very
production of life
till then, the total activity
on which
it was based), then, as far as practical development is concerned, it is
absolutely immaterial whether the idea of this revolution has been
expressed a hundred times already, as the history of communism
proves.
The Inconsistency of the Idealist Conception of History in General, and of German Post-Hegelian Philosophy in Particular
¶In the whole conception of history up to the present this real basis
of history has either been totally neglected or else considered as a
minor matter quite irrelevant to the course of history. History must,
therefore, always be written according to an extraneous standard; the
real production of life seems to be primeval history, while the truly
historical appears to be separated from ordinary life, something
extra-superterrestrial. With this the relation of man to nature is
excluded from history and hence the antithesis of nature and history is
created. The exponents of this conception of history have consequently
only been able to see in history the political actions of princes and
States, religious and all sorts of theoretical struggles, and in
particular in each historical epoch have had to share the illusion of
that epoch. For instance, if an epoch imagines itself to be actuated by
purely political
or religious
motives, although
religion
and politics
are only forms of its true motives,
the historian accepts this opinion. The idea,
the
conception
of the people in question about their real practice,
is transformed into the sole determining, active force, which controls
and determines their practice. When the crude form in which the division
of labour appears with the Indians and Egyptians calls forth the
caste-system in their State and religion, the historian believes that
the caste-system is the power which has produced this crude social
form.
¶While the French and the English at least hold by the political
illusion, which is moderately close to reality, the Germans move in the
realm of the pure spirit,
and make religious illusion the driving
force of history. The Hegelian philosophy of history is the last
consequence, reduced to its finest expression,
of all this German
historiography, for which it is not a question of real, nor even of
political, interests, but of pure thoughts, which consequently must
appear to Saint Bruno as a series of thoughts
that devour one
another and are finally swallowed up in self-consciousness.
– and
even more consistently the course of history must appear to Saint Max
Stirner, who knows not a thing about real history, as a mere tale of
knights, robbers and ghosts,
3 from whose visions he
can, of course, only save himself by unholiness
. This conception
is truly religious: it postulates religious man as the primitive man,
the starting-point of history, and in its imagination puts the religious
production of fancies in the place of the real production of the means
of subsistence and of life itself.
¶This whole conception of history, together with its dissolution and
the scruples and qualms resulting from it, is a purely national affair
of the Germans and has merely local interest for Germany, as for
instance the important question which has been under discussion in
recent times: how exactly one passes from the realm of God to the
realm of Man
– as if this realm of God
had ever existed
anywhere save in the imagination, and the learned gentlemen, without
being aware of it, were not constantly living in the realm of Man
to which they are now seeking the way; and as if the learned pastime
(for it is nothing more) of explaining the mystery of this theoretical
bubble-blowing did not on the contrary lie in demonstrating its origin
in actual earthly relations. For these Germans, it is altogether simply
a matter of resolving the ready-made nonsense they find into some other
freak, i.e., of presupposing that all this nonsense has a special sense
which can be discovered; while really it is only a question of
explaining these theoretical phrases from the actual existing relations.
The real, practical dissolution of these phrases, the removal of these
notions from the consciousness of men, will, as we have already said, be
effected by altered circumstances, not by theoretical deductions. For
the mass of men, i.e., the proletariat, these theoretical notions do not
exist and hence do not require to be dissolved, and if this mass ever
had any theoretical notions, e.g., religion, these have now long been
dissolved by circumstances.
¶The purely national character of these questions and solutions is
moreover shown by the fact that these theorists believe in all
seriousness that chimeras like the God-Man,
Man,
etc.,
have presided over individual epochs of history (Saint Bruno even goes
so far as to assert that only criticism and critics have made
history,
and when they themselves construct historical systems, they
skip over all earlier periods in the greatest haste and pass immediately
from Mongolism
to history with meaningful content,
that is
to say, to the history, of the Hallische and Deutsche Jahrbücher and the
dissolution of the Hegelian school into a general squabble. They forget
all other nations, all real events, and the theatrum mundi is confined
to the Leipzig book fair and the mutual quarrels of criticism,
[Bruno Bauer] man,
[Ludwig Feuerbach] and the unique
. [Max
Stirner] If for once these theorists treat really historical subjects,
as for instance the eighteenth century, they merely give a history of
ideas, separated from the facts and the practical development underlying
them; and even that merely in order to represent that period as an
imperfect preliminary stage, the as yet limited predecessor of the truly
historical age, i.e., the period of the German philosophic struggle from
1840 to 1844. As might be expected when the history of an earlier period
is written with the aim of accentuating the brilliance of an unhistoric
person and his fantasies, all the really historic events, even the
really historic interventions of politics in history, receive no
mention. Instead we get a narrative based not on research but on
arbitrary constructions and literary gossip, such as Saint Bruno
provided in his now forgotten history of the eighteenth century. These
pompous and arrogant hucksters of ideas, who imagine themselves
infinitely exalted above all national prejudices, are thus in practice
far more national than the beer-swilling philistines who dream of a
united Germany. They do not recognise the deeds of other nations as
historical; they live in Germany, within Germany 1281 and for Germany;
they turn the Rhine-song4 into a religious hymn and conquer
Alsace and Lorraine by robbing French philosophy instead of the French
state, by Germanising French ideas instead of French provinces. Herr
Venedey is a cosmopolitan compared with the Saints Bruno and Max, who,
in the universal dominance of theory, proclaim the universal dominance
of Germany.
§ Feuerbach: Philosophic, and Real, Liberation
¶[…] It is also clear from these arguments how grossly Feuerbach is
deceiving himself when (Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, 1845, Band 2) by
virtue of the qualification common man
he declares himself a
communist,[26] transforms the latter into a predicate of man,
and
thereby thinks it possible to change the word communist,
which in
the real world means the follower of a definite revolutionary party,
into a mere category. Feuerbach’s whole deduction with regard to the
relation of men to one another goes only so far as to prove that men
need and always have needed each other. He wants to establish
consciousness of this fact, that is to say, like the other theorists,
merely to produce a correct consciousness about an existing fact;
whereas for the real communist it is a question of overthrowing the
existing state of things. We thoroughly appreciate, moreover, that
Feuerbach, in endeavouring to produce consciousness of just this fact,
is going as far as a theorist possibly can, without ceasing to be a
theorist and philosopher…
¶As an example of Feuerbach’s acceptance and at the same time
misunderstanding of existing reality, which he still shares with our
opponents, we recall the passage in the Philosophie der Zukunft where he
develops the view that the existence of a thing or a man is at the same
time its or his essence, that the conditions of existence, the mode of
life and activity of an animal or human individual are those in which
its essence
feels itself satisfied. Here every exception is
expressly conceived as an unhappy chance, as an abnormality which cannot
be altered. Thus if millions of proletarians feel by no means contented
with their living conditions, if their existence
does not in the
least correspond to their essence,
then, according to the passage
quoted, this is an unavoidable misfortune, which must be borne quietly.
The millions of proletarians and communists, however, think differently
and will prove this in time, when they bring their existence
into
harmony with their essence
in a practical way, by means of a
revolution. Feuerbach, therefore, never speaks of the world of man in
such cases, but always takes refuge in external nature, and moreover in
nature which has not yet been subdued by men. But every new invention,
every advance made by industry, detaches another piece from this domain,
so that the ground which produces examples illustrating such
Feuerbachian propositions is steadily shrinking.
¶The essence
of the fish is its being,
water – to go no
further than this one proposition. The essence
of the freshwater
fish is the water of a river. But the latter ceases to be the
essence
of the fish and is no longer a suitable medium of
existence as soon as the river is made to serve industry, as soon as it
is polluted by dyes and other waste products and navigated by
steamboats, or as soon as its water is diverted into canals where simple
drainage can deprive the fish of its medium of existence. The
explanation that all such contradictions are inevitable abnormalities
does not essentially differ from the consolation which Saint Max Stirner
offers to the discontented, saving that this contradiction is their own
contradiction and this predicament their own predicament, whereupon
then, should either set their minds at ease, keep their disgust to
themselves, or revolt against it in some fantastic way. It differs just
as little from Saint Bruno’s allegation that these unfortunate
circumstances are due to the fact that those concerned are stuck in the
muck of substance,
have not advanced to “absolute
self-consciousness and do not realise that these adverse conditions are
spirit of their spirit.
§ Preconditions of the Real Liberation of Man
¶We shall, of course, not take the trouble to enlighten our wise
philosophers by explaining to them that the liberation
of man is
not advanced a single step by reducing philosophy, theology, substance
and all the trash to self-consciousness
and by liberating man
from the domination of these phrases, which have never held him in
thrall. Nor will we explain to them that it is only possible to achieve
real liberation in the real world and by employing real means, that
slavery cannot be abolished without the steam-engine and the mule and
spinning-jenny, serfdom cannot be abolished without improved
agriculture, and that, in general, people cannot be liberated as long as
they are unable to obtain food and drink, housing and clothing in
adequate quality and quantity. Liberation
is an historical and
not a mental act, and it is brought about by historical conditions, the
development of industry, commerce, agriculture, the conditions of
intercourse…[There is here a gap in the manuscript]
¶In Germany, a country where only a trivial historical development is taking place, these mental developments, these glorified and ineffective trivialities, naturally serve as a substitute for the lack of historical development, and they take root and have to be combated. But this fight is of local importance.
Feuerbach’s Contemplative and Inconsistent Materialism
¶In reality and for the practical materialist, i.e. the communist, it
is a question of revolutionising the existing world, of practically
attacking and changing existing things. When occasionally we find such
views with Feuerbach, they are never more than isolated surmises and
have much too little influence on his general outlook to be considered
here as anything else than embryos capable of development. Feuerbach’s
conception of the sensuous world is confined on the one hand to mere
contemplation of it, and on the other to mere feeling; he says
Man
instead of real historical man.
Man
is really
the German.
In the first case, the contemplation of the sensuous
world, he necessarily lights on things which contradict his
consciousness and feeling, which disturb the harmony he presupposes, the
harmony of all parts of the sensuous world and especially of man and
nature. To remove this disturbance, he must take refuge in a double
perception, a profane one which only perceives the flatly obvious
and a higher, philosophical, one which perceives the true essence
of things. He does not see how the sensuous world around him is, not a
thing given direct from all eternity, remaining ever the same, but the
product of industry and of the state of society; and, indeed, in the
sense that it is an historical product, the result of the activity of a
whole succession of generations, each standing on the shoulders of the
preceding one, developing its industry and its intercourse, modifying
its social system according to the changed needs. Even the objects of
the simplest sensuous certainty
are only given him through social
development, industry and commercial intercourse. The cherry-tree, like
almost all fruit-trees, was, as is well known, only a few centuries ago
transplanted by commerce into our zone, and therefore only by this
action of a definite society in a definite age it has become sensuous
certainty
for Feuerbach.
¶Incidentally, when we conceive things thus, as they really are and
happened, every profound philosophical problem is resolved, as will be
seen even more clearly later, quite simply into an empirical fact. For
instance, the important question of the relation of man to nature (Bruno
[Bauer] goes so far as to speak of the antitheses in nature and
history
(p. 110), as though these were two separate things
and man did not always have before him an historical nature and a
natural history) out of which all the unfathomably lofty works
on
substance
and self-consciousness
were born, crumbles of
itself when we understand that the celebrated unity of man with
nature
has always existed in industry and has existed in varying
forms in every epoch according to the lesser or greater development of
industry, just like the struggle
of man with nature, right up to
the development of his productive powers on a corresponding basis.
Industry and commerce, production and the exchange of the necessities of
life, themselves determine distribution, the structure of the different
social classes and are, in turn, determined by it as to the mode in
which they are carried on; and so it happens that in Manchester, for
instance, Feuerbach sees only factories and machines, where a hundred
years ago only spinning-wheels and weaving-rooms were to be seen, or in
the Campagna of Rome he finds only pasture lands and swamps, where in
the time of Augustus he would have found nothing but the vineyards and
villas of Roman capitalists. Feuerbach speaks in particular of the
perception of natural science; he mentions secrets which are disclosed
only to the eye of the physicist and chemist; but where would natural
science be without industry and commerce? Even this pure natural science
is provided with an aim, as with its material, only through trade and
industry, through the sensuous activity of men. So much is this
activity, this unceasing sensuous labour and creation, this production,
the basis of the whole sensuous world as it now exists, that, were it
interrupted only for a year, Feuerbach would not only find an enormous
change in the natural world, but would very soon find that the whole
world of men and his own perceptive faculty, nay his own existence, were
missing. Of course, in all this the priority of external nature remains
unassailed, and all this has no application to the original men produced
by generatio aequivoca [spontaneous generation]; but this
differentiation has meaning only insofar as man is considered to be
distinct from nature. For that matter, nature, the nature that preceded
human history, is not by any means the nature in which Feuerbach lives,
it is nature which today no longer exists anywhere (except perhaps on a
few Australian coral-islands of recent origin) and which, therefore,
does not exist for Feuerbach.
¶Certainly Feuerbach has a great advantage over the pure
materialists in that he realises how man too is an object of the
senses.
But apart from the fact that he only conceives him as an
object of the senses, not as sensuous activity,
because he still
remains in the realm of theory and conceives of men not in their given
social connection, not under their existing conditions of life, which
have made them what they are, he never arrives at the really existing
active men, but stops at the abstraction man,
and gets no further
than recognising the true, individual, corporeal man,
emotionally, i.e. he knows no other human relationships
of man
to man
than love and friendship, and even then idealised. He gives
no criticism of the present conditions of life. Thus he never manages to
conceive the sensuous world as the total living sensuous activity of the
individuals composing it; and therefore when, for example, he sees
instead of healthy men a crowd of scrofulous, overworked and consumptive
starvelings, he is compelled to take refuge in the higher
perception
and in the ideal compensation in the species,
and
thus to relapse into idealism at the very point where the communist
materialist sees the necessity, and at the same time the condition, of a
transformation both of industry and of the social structure.
¶As far as Feuerbach is a materialist he does not deal with history, and as far as he considers history he is not a materialist. With him materialism and history diverge completely, a fact which incidentally is already obvious from what has been said.
§ Ruling Class and Ruling Ideas
¶The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas,
i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the
same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means
of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time
over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally
speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are
subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal
expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material
relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make
the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The
individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things
consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as
a class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is
self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other
things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the
production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas
are the ruling ideas of the epoch. For instance, in an age and in a
country where royal power, aristocracy, and bourgeoisie are contending
for mastery and where, therefore, mastery is shared, the doctrine of the
separation of powers proves to be the dominant idea and is expressed as
an eternal law.
¶The division of labour, which we already saw above as one of the chief forces of history up till now, manifests itself also in the ruling class as the division of mental and material labour, so that inside this class one part appears as the thinkers of the class (its active, conceptive ideologists, who make the perfecting of the illusion of the class about itself their chief source of livelihood), while the others’ attitude to these ideas and illusions is more passive and receptive, because they are in reality the active members of this class and have less time to make up illusions and ideas about themselves. Within this class this cleavage can even develop into a certain opposition and hostility between the two parts, which, however, in the case of a practical collision, in which the class itself is endangered, automatically comes to nothing, in which case there also vanishes the semblance that the ruling ideas were not the ideas of the ruling class and had a power distinct from the power of this class. The existence of revolutionary ideas in a particular period presupposes the existence of a revolutionary class; about the premises for the latter sufficient has already been said above.
¶If now in considering the course of history we detach the ideas of the ruling class from the ruling class itself and attribute to them an independent existence, if we confine ourselves to saying that these or those ideas were dominant at a given time, without bothering ourselves about the conditions of production and the producers of these ideas, if we thus ignore the individuals and world conditions which are the source of the ideas, we can say, for instance, that during the time that the aristocracy was dominant, the concepts honour, loyalty, etc. were dominant, during the dominance of the bourgeoisie the concepts freedom, equality, etc. The ruling class itself on the whole imagines this to be so. This conception of history, which is common to all historians, particularly since the eighteenth century, will necessarily come up against the phenomenon that increasingly abstract ideas hold sway, i.e. ideas which increasingly take on the form of universality. For each new class which puts itself in the place of one ruling before it, is compelled, merely in order to carry through its aim, to represent its interest as the common interest of all the members of society, that is, expressed in ideal form: it has to give its ideas the form of universality, and represent them as the only rational, universally valid ones. The class making a revolution appears from the very start, if only because it is opposed to a class, not as a class but as the representative of the whole of society; it appears as the whole mass of society confronting the one ruling class. It can do this because, to start with, its interest really is more connected with the common interest of all other non-ruling classes, because under the pressure of hitherto existing conditions its interest has not yet been able to develop as the particular interest of a particular class. Its victory, therefore, benefits also many individuals of the other classes which are not winning a dominant position, but only insofar as it now puts these individuals in a position to raise themselves into the ruling class. When the French bourgeoisie overthrew the power of the aristocracy, it thereby made it possible for many proletarians to raise themselves above the proletariat, but only insofar as they become bourgeois. Every new class, therefore, achieves its hegemony only on a broader basis than that of the class ruling previously, whereas the opposition of the non-ruling class against the new ruling class later develops all the more sharply and profoundly. Both these things determine the fact that the struggle to be waged against this new ruling class, in its turn, aims at a more decided and radical negation of the previous conditions of society than could all previous classes which sought to rule.
¶This whole semblance, that the rule of a certain class is only the
rule of certain ideas, comes to a natural end, of course, as soon as
class rule in general ceases to be the form in which society is
organised, that is to say, as soon as it is no longer necessary to
represent a particular interest as general or the general
interest
as ruling.
¶Once the ruling ideas have been separated from the ruling individuals
and, above all, from the relationships which result from a given stage
of the mode of production, and in this way the conclusion has been
reached that history is always under the sway of ideas, it is very easy
to abstract from these various ideas the idea,
the notion, etc.
as the dominant force in history, and thus to understand all these
separate ideas and concepts as forms of self-determination
on the
part of the concept developing in history. It follows then naturally,
too, that all the relationships of men can be derived from the concept
of man, man as conceived, the essence of man, Man. This has been done by
the speculative philosophers. Hegel himself confesses at the end of the
Geschichtsphilosophie that he has considered the progress of the
concept only
and has represented in history the true
theodicy.
(p.446.) Now one can go back again to the producers of the
concept,
to the theorists, ideologists and philosophers, and one
comes then to the conclusion that the philosophers, the thinkers as
such, have at all times been dominant in history: a conclusion, as we
see5, already expressed by Hegel. The
whole trick of proving the hegemony of the spirit in history (hierarchy
Stirner calls it) is thus confined to the following three efforts.
- One must separate the ideas of those ruling for empirical reasons, under empirical conditions and as empirical individuals, from these actual rulers, and thus recognise the rule of ideas or illusions in history.
- One must bring an order into this rule of ideas, prove a mystical
connection among the successive ruling ideas, which is managed by
understanding them as
acts of self-determination on the part of the concept
(this is possible because by virtue of their empirical basis these ideas are really connected with one another and because, conceived as mere ideas, they become self-distinctions, distinctions made by thought). - To remove the mystical appearance of this
self-determining concept
it is changed into a person –Self-Consciousness
– or, to appear thoroughly materialistic, into a series of persons, who represent theconcept
in history, into thethinkers,
thephilosophers,
the ideologists, who again are understood as the manufacturers of history, as thecouncil of guardians,
as the rulers. Thus the whole body of materialistic elements has been removed from history and now full rein can be given to the speculative steed.
¶Whilst in ordinary life every shopkeeper is very well able to distinguish between what somebody professes to be and what he really is, our historians have not yet won even this trivial insight. They take every epoch at its word and believe that everything it says and imagines about itself is true.
¶This historical method which reigned in Germany, and especially the reason why, must be understood from its connection with the illusion of ideologists in general, e.g. the illusions of the jurist, politicians (of the practical statesmen among them, too), from the dogmatic dreamings and distortions of these fellows; this is explained perfectly easily from their practical position in life, their job, and the division of labour.
§ The Real Basis of Ideology
§ Division of Labour: Town and Country6
¶From the first there follows the premise of a highly developed division of labour and an extensive commerce; from the second, the locality. In the first case the individuals must be brought together; in the second they find themselves alongside the given instrument of production as instruments of production themselves. Here, therefore, arises the difference between natural instruments of production and those created by civilisation. The field (water, etc.) can be regarded as a natural instrument of production. In the first case, that of the natural instrument of production, individuals are subservient to nature; in the second, to a product of labour. In the first case, therefore, property (landed property) appears as direct natural domination, in the second, as domination of labour, particularly of accumulated labour, capital. The first case presupposes that the individuals are united by some bond: family, tribe, the land itself, etc.; the second, that they are independent of one another and are only held together by exchange. In the first case, what is involved is chiefly an exchange between men and nature in which the labour of the former is exchanged for the products of the latter; in the second, it is predominantly an exchange of men among themselves. In the first case, average, human common sense is adequate – physical activity is as yet not separated from mental activity; in the second, the division between physical and mental labour must already be practically completed. In the first case, the domination of the proprietor over the propertyless may be based on a personal relationship, on a kind of community; in the second, it must have taken on a material shape in a third party – money. In the first case, small industry exists, but determined by the utilisation of the natural instrument of production and therefore without the distribution of labour among various individuals; in the second, industry exists only in and through the division of labour.
The Division of Material and Mental Labour. Separation of Town and Country, The Guild System
¶The greatest division of material and mental labour is the separation of town and country. The antagonism between town and country begins with the transition from barbarism to civilisation, from tribe to State, from locality to nation, and runs through the whole history of civilisation to the present day (the Anti-Corn Law League).
¶The existence of the town implies, at the same time, the necessity of administration, police, taxes, etc.; in short, of the municipality, and thus of politics in general. Here first became manifest the division of the population into two great classes, which is directly based on the division of labour and on the instruments of production. The town already is in actual fact the concentration of the population, of the instruments of production, of capital, of pleasures, of needs, while the country demonstrates just the opposite fact, isolation and separation. The antagonism between town and country can only exist within the framework of private property. It is the most crass expression of the subjection of the individual under the division of labour, under a definite activity forced upon him – a subjection which makes one man into a restricted town-animal, the other into a restricted country-animal, and daily creates anew the conflict between their interests. Labour is here again the chief thing, power over individuals, and as long as the latter exists, private property must exist. The abolition of the antagonism between town and country is one of the first conditions of communal life, a condition which again depends on a mass of material premises and which cannot be fulfilled by the mere will, as anyone can see at the first glance. (These conditions have still to be enumerated.) The separation of town and country can also be understood as the separation of capital and landed property, as the beginning of the existence and development of capital independent of landed property – the beginning of property having its basis only in labour and exchange.
¶In the towns which, in the Middle Ages, did not derive ready-made from an earlier period but were formed anew by the serfs who had become free, each man’s own particular labour was his only property apart from the small capital he brought with him, consisting almost solely of the most necessary tools of his craft. The competition of serfs constantly escaping into the town, the constant war of the country against the towns and thus the necessity of an organised municipal military force, the bond of common ownership in a particular kind of labour, the necessity of common buildings for the sale of their wares at a time when craftsmen were also traders, and the consequent exclusion of the unauthorised from these buildings, the conflict among the interests of the various crafts, the necessity of protecting their laboriously acquired skill, and the feudal organisation of the whole of the country: these were the causes of the union of the workers of each craft in guilds. We have not at this point to go further into the manifold modifications of the guild-system, which arise through later historical developments. The flight of the serfs into the towns went on without interruption right through the Middle Ages. These serfs, persecuted by their lords in the country, came separately into the towns, where they found an organised community, against which they were powerless and in which they had to subject themselves to the station assigned to them by the demand for their labour and the interest of their organised urban competitors. These workers, entering separately, were never able to attain to any power, since, if their labour was of the guild type which had to be learned, the guild-masters bent them to their will and organised them according to their interest; or if their labour was not such as had to be learned, and therefore not of the guild type, they became day-labourers and never managed to organise, remaining an unorganised rabble. The need for day-labourers in the towns created the rabble.
¶These towns were true associations
, called forth by the direct
need, the care of providing for the protection of property, and of
multiplying the means of production and defence of the separate members.
The rabble of these towns was devoid of any power, composed as it was of
individuals strange to one another who had entered separately, and who
stood unorganised over against an organised power, armed for war, and
jealously watching over them. The journeymen and apprentices were
organised in each craft as it best suited the interest of the masters.
The patriarchal relationship existing between them and their masters
gave the latter a double power – on the one hand because of their
influence on the whole life of the journeymen, and on the other because,
for the journeymen who worked with the same master, it was a real bond
which held them together against the journeymen of other masters and
separated them from these. And finally, the journeymen were bound to the
existing order by their simple interest in becoming masters themselves.
While, therefore, the rabble at least carried out revolts against the
whole municipal order, revolts which remained completely ineffective
because of their powerlessness, the journeymen never got further than
small acts of insubordination within separate guilds, such as belong to
the very nature of the guild-system. The great risings of the Middle
Ages all radiated from the country, but equally remained totally
ineffective because of the isolation and consequent crudity of the
peasants.
¶In the towns, the division of labour between the individual guilds was as yet [quite naturally derived] and, in the guilds themselves, not at all developed between the individual workers. Every workman had to be versed in a whole round of tasks, had to be able to make everything that was to be made with his tools. The limited commerce and the scanty communication between the individual towns, the lack of population and the narrow needs did not allow of a higher division of labour, and therefore every man who wished to become a master had to be proficient in the whole of his craft. Thus there is found with medieval craftsmen an interest in their special work and in proficiency in it, which was capable of rising to a narrow artistic sense. For this very reason, however, every medieval craftsman was completely absorbed in his work, to which he had a contented, slavish relationship, and to which he was subjected to a far greater extent than the modern worker, whose work is a matter of indifference to him.
¶Capital in these towns was a naturally derived capital, consisting of a house, the tools of the craft, and the natural, hereditary customers; and not being realisable, on account of the backwardness of commerce and the lack of circulation, it descended from father to son. Unlike modern capital, which can be assessed in money and which may be indifferently invested in this thing or that, this capital was directly connected with the particular work of the owner, inseparable from it and to this extent estate capital.
§ Further Division of Labour
¶The next extension of the division of labour was the separation of production and commerce, the formation of a special class of merchants; a separation which, in the towns bequeathed by a former period, had been handed down (among other things with the Jews) and which very soon appeared in the newly formed ones. With this there was given the possibility of commercial communications transcending the immediate neighbourhood, a possibility, the realisation of which depended on the existing means of communication, the state of public safety in the countryside, which was determined by political conditions (during the whole of the Middle Ages, as is well known, the merchants travelled in armed caravans), and on the cruder or more advanced needs (determined by the stage of culture attained) of the region accessible to intercourse.
¶With commerce the prerogative of a particular class, with the extension of trade through the merchants beyond the immediate surroundings of the town, there immediately appears a reciprocal action between production and commerce. The towns enter into relations with one another, new tools are brought from one town into the other, and the separation between production and commerce soon calls forth a new division of production between the individual towns, each of which is soon exploiting a predominant branch of industry. The local restrictions of earlier times begin gradually to be broken down.
¶It depends purely on the extension of commerce whether the productive forces achieved in a locality, especially inventions, are lost for later development or not. As long as there exists no commerce transcending the immediate neighbourhood, every invention must be made separately in each locality, and mere chances such as irruptions of barbaric peoples, even ordinary wars, are sufficient to cause a country with advanced productive forces and needs to have to start right over again from the beginning. In primitive history every invention had to be made daily anew and in each locality independently. How little highly developed productive forces are safe from complete destruction, given even a relatively very extensive commerce, is proved by the Phoenicians, whose inventions were for the most part lost for a long time to come through the ousting of this nation from commerce, its conquest by Alexander and its consequent decline. Likewise, for instance, glass-painting in the Middle Ages. Only when commerce has become world commerce and has as its basis large-scale industry, when all nations are drawn into the competitive struggle, is the permanence of the acquired productive forces assured.
§ The Rise of Manufacturing
¶The immediate consequence of the division of labour between the various towns was the rise of manufactures, branches of production which had outgrown the guild-system. Manufactures first flourished, in Italy and later in Flanders, under the historical premise of commerce with foreign nations. In other countries, England and France for example, manufactures were at first confined to the home market. Besides the premises already mentioned manufactures depend on an already advanced concentration of population, particularly in the countryside, and of capital, which began to accumulate in the hands of individuals, partly in the guilds in spite of the guild regulations, partly among the merchants.
¶That labour which from the first presupposed a machine, even of the crudest sort, soon showed itself the most capable of development. Weaving, earlier carried on in the country by the peasants as a secondary occupation to procure their clothing, was the first labour to receive an impetus and a further development through the extension of commerce. Weaving was the first and remained the principal manufacture. The rising demand for clothing materials, consequent on the growth of population, the growing accumulation and mobilisation of natural capital through accelerated circulation, the demand for luxuries called forth by the latter and favoured generally by the gradual extension of commerce, gave weaving a quantitative and qualitative stimulus, which wrenched it out of the form of production hitherto existing. Alongside the peasants weaving for their own use, who continued, and still continue, with this sort of work, there emerged a new class of weavers in the towns, whose fabrics were destined for the whole home market and usually for foreign markets too.
¶Weaving, an occupation demanding in most cases little skill and soon splitting up into countless branches, by its whole nature resisted the trammels of the guild. Weaving was, therefore, carried on mostly in villages and market-centres without guild organisation, which gradually became towns, and indeed the most flourishing towns in each land.
¶With guild-free manufacture, property relations also quickly changed. The first advance beyond naturally derived estate capital was provided by the rise of merchants whose capital was from the beginning movable, capital in the modern sense as far as one can speak of it, given the circumstances of those times. The second advance came with manufacture, which again made mobile a mass of natural capital, and altogether increased the mass of movable capital as against that of natural capital.
¶At the same time, manufacture became a refuge of the peasants from the guilds which excluded them or paid them badly, just as earlier the guild-towns had [served] as a refuge for the peasants from [the oppressive landed nobility].
¶Simultaneously with the beginning of manufactures there was a period of vagabondage caused by the abolition of the feudal bodies of retainers, the disbanding of the swollen armies which had flocked to serve the kings against their vassals, the improvement of agriculture, and the transformation of great strips of tillage into pasture land. From this alone it is clear how this vagabondage is strictly connected with the disintegration of the feudal system. As early as the thirteenth century we find isolated epochs of this kind, but only at the end of the fifteenth and beginning of the sixteenth does this vagabondage make a general and permanent appearance. These vagabonds, who were so numerous that, for instance, Henry VIII of England had 72,000 of them hanged, were only prevailed upon to work with the greatest difficulty and through the most extreme necessity, and then only after long resistance. The rapid rise of manufactures, particularly in England, absorbed them gradually.
¶With the advent of manufactures, the various nations entered into a competitive relationship, the struggle for trade, which was fought out in wars, protective duties and prohibitions, whereas earlier the nations, insofar as they were connected at all, had carried on an inoffensive exchange with each other. Trade had from now on a political significance.
¶With the advent of manufacture the relationship between worker and employer changed. In the guilds the patriarchal relationship between journeyman and master continued to exist; in manufacture its place was taken by the monetary relation between worker and capitalist – a relationship which in the countryside and in small towns retained a patriarchal tinge, but in the larger, the real manufacturing towns, quite early lost almost all patriarchal complexion.
¶Manufacture and the movement of production in general received an enormous impetus through the extension of commerce which came with the discovery of America and the sea-route to the East Indies. The new products imported thence, particularly the masses of gold and silver which came into circulation and totally changed the position of the classes towards one another, dealing a hard blow to feudal landed property and to the workers; the expeditions of adventurers, colonisation; and above all the extension of markets into a world market, which had now become possible and was daily becoming more and more a fact, called forth a new phase of historical development, into which in general we cannot here enter further. Through the colonisation of the newly discovered countries the commercial struggle of the nations amongst one another was given new fuel and accordingly greater extension and animosity.
¶The expansion of trade and manufacture accelerated the accumulation of movable capital, while in the guilds, which were not stimulated to extend their production, natural capital remained stationary or even declined. Trade and manufacture created the big bourgeoisie; in the guilds was concentrated the petty bourgeoisie, which no longer was dominant in the towns as formerly, but had to bow to the might of the great merchants and manufacturers. Hence the decline of the guilds, as soon as they came into contact with manufacture.
¶The intercourse of nations took on, in the epoch of which we have been speaking, two different forms. At first the small quantity of gold and silver in circulation involved the ban on the export of these metals; and industry, for the most part imported from abroad and made necessary by the need for employing the growing urban population, could not do without those privileges which could be granted not only, of course, against home competition, but chiefly against foreign. The local guild privilege was in these original prohibitions extended over the whole nation. Customs duties originated from the tributes which the feudal lords exacted as protective levies against robbery from merchants passing through their territories, tributes later imposed likewise by the towns, and which, with the rise of the modern states, were the Treasury’s most obvious means of raising money.
¶The appearance of American gold and silver on the European markets, the gradual development of industry, the rapid expansion of trade and the consequent rise of the non-guild bourgeoisie and of money, gave these measures another significance. The State, which was daily less and less able to do without money, now retained the ban on the export of gold and silver out of fiscal considerations; the bourgeois, for whom these masses of money which were hurled onto the market became the chief object of speculative buying, were thoroughly content with this; privileges established earlier became a source of income for the government and were sold for money; in the customs legislation there appeared the export duty, which, since it only [placed] a hindrance in the way of industry, had a purely fiscal aim.
¶The second period began in the middle of the seventeenth century and lasted almost to the end of the eighteenth. Commerce and navigation had expanded more rapidly than manufacture, which played a secondary role; the colonies were becoming considerable consumers; and after long struggles the separate nations shared out the opening world market among themselves. This period begins with the Navigation Laws7 and colonial monopolies. The competition of the nations among themselves was excluded as far as possible by tariffs, prohibitions and treaties; and in the last resort the competitive struggle was carried on and decided by wars (especially naval wars). The mightiest maritime nation, the English, retained preponderance in trade and manufacture. Here, already, we find concentration in one country.
¶Manufacture was all the time sheltered by protective duties in the
home market, by monopolies in the colonial market, and abroad as much as
possible by differential duties. The working-up of home-produced
material was encouraged (wool and linen in England, silk in France), the
export of home-produced raw material forbidden (wool in England), and
the [working-up] of imported material neglected or suppressed (cotton in
England). The nation dominant in sea trade and colonial power naturally
secured for itself also the greatest quantitative and qualitative
expansion of manufacture. Manufacture could not be carried on without
protection, since, if the slightest change takes place in other
countries, it can lose its market and be ruined; under reasonably
favourable conditions it may easily be introduced into a country, but
for this very reason can easily be destroyed. At the same time through
the mode in which it is carried on, particularly in the eighteenth
century, in the countryside, it is to such an extent interwoven with the
vital relationships of a great mass of individuals, that no country dare
jeopardise its existence by permitting free competition. Insofar as it
manages to export, it therefore depends entirely on the extension or
restriction of commerce, and exercises a relatively very small reaction
[on the latter]. Hence its secondary [importance] and the influence of
[the merchants] in the eighteenth century. It was the merchants and
especially the shippers who more than anybody else pressed for State
protection and monopolies; the manufacturers also demanded and indeed
received protection, but all the time were inferior in political
importance to the merchants. The commercial towns, particularly the
maritime towns, became to some extent civilised and acquired the outlook
of the big bourgeoisie, but in the factory towns an extreme
petty-bourgeois outlook persisted. Cf Aikin,8
etc. The eighteenth century was the century of trade. Pinto says this
expressly: Le commerce fait la marotte du siècle
[Commerce is
the rage of the century.
]; and: Depuis quelque temps il n’est
plus question que de commerce, de navgation et de marine.
[For
some time now people have been talking only about commerce, navigation
and the navy.
]
¶This period is also characterised by the cessation of the bans on the export of gold and silver and the beginning of the trade in money; by banks, national debts, paper money; by speculation in stocks and shares and stockjobbing in all articles; by the development of finance in general. Again capital lost a great part of the natural character which had still clung to it.
Most Extensive Division of Labour. Large-Scale Industry
¶The concentration of trade and manufacture in one country, England, developing irresistibly in the seventeenth century, gradually created for this country a relative world market, and thus a demand for the manufactured products of this country, which could no longer be met by the industrial productive forces hitherto existing. This demand, outgrowing the productive forces, was the motive power which, by producing big industry – the application of elemental forces to industrial ends, machinery and the most complex division of labour – called into existence the third period of private ownership since the Middle Ages. There already existed in England the other pre-conditions of this new phase: freedom of competition inside the nation, the development of theoretical mechanics, etc. (Indeed, the science of mechanics perfected by Newton was altogether the most popular science in France and England in the eighteenth century.) (Free competition inside the nation itself had everywhere to be conquered by a revolution – 1640 and 1688 in England, 1789 in France.)
¶Competition soon compelled every country that wished to retain its historical role to protect its manufactures by renewed customs regulations (the old duties were no longer any good against big industry) and soon after to introduce big industry under protective duties. Big industry universalised competition in spite of these protective measures (it is practical free trade; the protective duty is only a palliative, a measure of defence within free trade), established means of communication and the modern world market, subordinated trade to itself, transformed all capital into industrial capital, and thus produced the rapid circulation (development of the financial system) and the centralisation of capital. By universal competition it forced all individuals to strain their energy to the utmost. It destroyed as far as possible ideology, religion, morality, etc. and where it could not do this, made them into a palpable lie. It produced world history for the first time, insofar as it made all civilised nations and every individual member of them dependent for the satisfaction of their wants on the whole world, thus destroying the former natural exclusiveness of separate nations. It made natural science subservient to capital and took from the division of labour the last semblance of its natural character. It destroyed natural growth in general, as far as this is possible while labour exists, and resolved all natural relationships into money relationships. In the place of naturally grown towns it created the modern, large industrial cities which have sprung up overnight. Wherever it penetrated, it destroyed the crafts and all earlier stages of industry. It completed the victory of the commercial town over the countryside. [Its first premise] was the automatic system. [Its development] produced a mass of productive forces, for which private [property] became just as much a fetter as the guild had been for manufacture and the small, rural workshop for the developing craft. These productive forces received under the system of private property a one-sided development only, and became for the majority destructive forces; moreover, a great multitude of such forces could find no application at all within this system. Generally speaking, big industry created everywhere the same relations between the classes of society, and thus destroyed the peculiar individuality of the various nationalities. And finally, while the bourgeoisie of each nation still retained separate national interests, big industry created a class, which in all nations has the same interest and with which nationality is already dead; a class which is really rid of all the old world and at the same time stands pitted against it. Big industry makes for the worker not only the relation to the capitalist, but labour itself, unbearable.
¶It is evident that big industry does not reach the same level of development in all districts of a country. This does not, however, retard the class movement of the proletariat, because the proletarians created by big industry assume leadership of this movement and carry the whole mass along with them, and because the workers excluded from big industry are placed by it in a still worse situation than the workers in big industry itself. The countries in which big industry is developed act in a similar manner upon the more or less non-industrial countries, insofar as the latter are swept by universal commerce into the universal competitive struggle.9
¶These different forms are just so many forms of the organisation of labour, and hence of property. In each period a unification of the existing productive forces takes place, insofar as this has been rendered necessary by needs.
§ The Relation of State and Law to Property
¶The first form of property, in the ancient world as in the Middle
Ages, is tribal property, determined with the Romans chiefly by war,
with the Germans by the rearing of cattle. In the case of the ancient
peoples, since several tribes live together in one town, the tribal
property appears as State property, and the right of the individual to
it as mere possession
which, however, like tribal property as a
whole, is confined to landed property only. Real private property began
with the ancients, as with modern nations, with movable property. –
(Slavery and community) (dominium ex jure Quiritum10). In the case of the nations which
grew out of the Middle Ages, tribal property evolved through various
stages – feudal landed property, corporative movable property, capital
invested in manufacture – to modern capital, determined by big industry
and universal competition, i.e. pure private property, which has cast
off all semblance of a communal institution and has shut out the State
from any influence on the development of property. To this modern
private property corresponds the modern State, which, purchased
gradually by the owners of property by means of taxation, has fallen
entirely into their hands through the national debt, and its existence
has become wholly dependent on the commercial credit which the owners of
property, the bourgeois, extend to it, as reflected in the rise and fall
of State funds on the stock exchange. By the mere fact that it is a
class and no longer an estate, the bourgeoisie is forced to organise
itself no longer locally, but nationally, and to give a general form to
its mean average interest. Through the emancipation of private property
from the community, the State has become a separate entity, beside and
outside civil society; but it is nothing more than the form of
organisation which the bourgeois necessarily adopt both for internal and
external purposes, for the mutual guarantee of their property and
interests. The independence of the State is only found nowadays in those
countries where the estates have not yet completely developed into
classes, where the estates, done away with in more advanced countries,
still have a part to play, and where there exists a mixture; countries,
that is to say, in which no one section of the population can achieve
dominance over the others. This is the case particularly in Germany. The
most perfect example of the modern State is North America. The modern
French, English and American writers all express the opinion that the
State exists only for the sake of private property, so that this fact
has penetrated into the consciousness of the normal man.
¶Since the State is the form in which the individuals of a ruling class assert their common interests, and in which the whole civil society of an epoch is epitomised, it follows that the State mediates in the formation of all common institutions and that the institutions receive a political form. Hence the illusion that law is based on the will, and indeed on the will divorced from its real basis – on free will. Similarly, justice is in its turn reduced to the actual laws.
¶Civil law develops simultaneously with private property out of the disintegration of the natural community. With the Romans the development of private property and civil law had no further industrial and commercial consequences, because their whole mode of production did not alter. (Usury!)
¶With modern peoples, where the feudal community was disintegrated by industry and trade, there began with the rise of private property and civil law a new phase, which was capable of further development. The very first town which carried on an extensive maritime trade in the Middle Ages, Amalfi, also developed maritime law. As soon as industry and trade developed private property further, first in Italy and later in other countries, the highly developed Roman civil law was immediately adopted again and raised, to authority. When later the bourgeoisie had acquired so much power that the princes took up its interests in order to overthrow the feudal nobility by means of the bourgeoisie, there began in all countries – in France in the sixteenth century – the real development of law, which in all countries except England proceeded on the basis of the Roman Codex. In England, too, Roman legal principles had to be introduced to further the development of civil law (especially in the case of movable property). (It must not be forgotten that law has just as little an independent history as religion.)
¶In civil law the existing property relationships are declared to be the result of the general will. The jus utendi et abutendi11 itself asserts on the one hand the fact that private property has become entirely independent of the community, and on the other the illusion that private property itself is based solely on the private will, the arbitrary disposal of the thing. In practice, the abuti has very definite economic limitations for the owner of private property, if he does not wish to see his property and hence his jus abutendi pass into other hands, since actually the thing, considered merely with reference to his will, is not a thing at all, but only becomes a thing, true property in intercourse, and independently of the law (a relationship, which the philosophers call an idea). This juridical illusion, which reduces law to the mere will, necessarily leads, in the further development of property relationships, to the position that a man may have a legal title to a thing without really having the thing. If, for instance, the income from a piece of land is lost owing to competition, then the proprietor has certainly his legal title to it along with the jus utendi et abutendi. But he can do nothing with it: he owns nothing as a landed proprietor if in addition he has not enough capital to cultivate his ground. This illusion of the jurists also explains the fact that for them, as for every code, it is altogether fortuitous that individuals enter into relationships among themselves (e.g. contracts); it explains why they consider that these relationships [can] be entered into or not at will, and that their content rests purely on the individual [free] will of the contracting parties.
¶Whenever, through the development of industry and commerce, new forms of intercourse have been evolved (e.g. assurance companies, etc.), the law has always been compelled to admit them among the modes of acquiring property.
§ FORMS OF SOCIAL CONSCIOUSNESS12
Why the ideologists turn everything upside-down.
§ Proletarians and Communism
§ Individuals, Class, and Community
¶In the Middle Ages the citizens in each town were compelled to unite against the landed nobility to save their skins. The extension of trade, the establishment of communications, led the separate towns to get to know other towns, which had asserted the same interests in the struggle with the same antagonist. Out of the many local corporations of burghers there arose only gradually the burgher class. The conditions of life of the individual burghers became, on account of their contradiction to the existing relationships and of the mode of labour determined by these, conditions which were common to them all and independent of each individual. The burghers had created the conditions insofar as they had torn themselves free from feudal ties, and were created by them insofar as they were determined by their antagonism to the feudal system which they found in existence. When the individual towns began to enter into associations, these common conditions developed into class conditions. The same conditions, the same contradiction, the same interests necessarily called forth on the whole similar customs everywhere. The bourgeoisie itself with its conditions, develops only gradually, splits according to the division of labour into various fractions and finally absorbs all propertied classes it finds in existence13 (while it develops the majority of the earlier propertyless and a part of the hitherto propertied classes into a new class, the proletariat) in the measure to which all property found in existence is transformed into industrial or commercial capital. The separate individuals form a class only insofar as they have to carry on a common battle against another class; otherwise they are on hostile terms with each other as competitors. On the other hand, the class in its turn achieves an independent existence over against the individuals, so that the latter find their conditions of existence predestined, and hence have their position in life and their personal development assigned to them by their class, become subsumed under it. This is the same phenomenon as the subjection of the separate individuals to the division of labour and can only be removed by the abolition of private property and of labour itself. We have already indicated several times how this subsuming of individuals under the class brings with it their subjection to all kinds of ideas, etc.
¶If from a philosophical point of view one considers this evolution of
individuals in the common conditions of existence of estates and
classes, which followed on one another, and in the accompanying general
conceptions forced upon them, it is certainly very easy to imagine that
in these individuals the species, or Man
, has evolved, or that
they evolved Man
– and in this way one can give history some hard
clouts on the ear.14 One can conceive these various
estates and classes to be specific terms of the general expression,
subordinate varieties of the species, or evolutionary phases of
Man
.
¶This subsuming of individuals under definite classes cannot be abolished until a class has taken shape, which has no longer any particular class interest to assert against the ruling class.
¶The transformation, through the division of labour, of personal powers (relationships) into material powers, cannot be dispelled by dismissing the general idea of it from one’s mind, but can only be abolished by the individuals again subjecting these material powers to themselves and abolishing the division of labour. This is not possible without the community. Only in community [with others has each] individual the means of cultivating his gifts in all directions; only in the community, therefore, is personal freedom possible. In the previous substitutes for the community, in the State, etc. personal freedom has existed only for the individuals who developed within the relationships of the ruling class, and only insofar as they were individuals of this class. The illusory community, in which individuals have up till now combined, always took on an independent existence in relation to them, and was at the same time, since it was the combination of one class over against another, not only a completely illusory community, but a new fetter as well. In a real community the individuals obtain their freedom in and through their association.
¶Individuals have always built on themselves, but naturally on
themselves within their given historical conditions and relationships,
not on the pure
individual in the sense of the ideologists. But
in the course of historical evolution, and precisely through the
inevitable fact that within the division of labour social relationships
take on an independent existence, there appears a division within the
life of each individual, insofar as it is personal and insofar as it is
determined by some branch of labour and the conditions pertaining to it.
(We do not mean it to be understood from this that, for example, the
rentier, the capitalist, etc. cease to be persons; but their personality
is conditioned and determined by quite definite class relationships, and
the division appears only in their opposition to another class and, for
themselves, only when they go bankrupt.) In the estate (and even more in
the tribe) this is as yet concealed: for instance, a nobleman always
remains a nobleman, a commoner always a commoner, apart from his other
relationships, a quality inseparable from his individuality. The
division between the personal and the class individual, the accidental
nature of the conditions of life for the individual, appears only with
the emergence of the class, which is itself a product of the
bourgeoisie. This accidental character is only engendered and developed
by competition and the struggle of individuals among themselves. Thus,
in imagination, individuals seem freer under the dominance of the
bourgeoisie than before, because their conditions of life seem
accidental; in reality, of course, they are less free, because they are
more subjected to the violence of things. The difference from the estate
comes out particularly in the antagonism between the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat. When the estate of the urban burghers, the corporations,
etc. emerged in opposition to the landed nobility, their condition of
existence – movable property and craft labour, which had already existed
latently before their separation from the feudal ties – appeared as
something positive, which was asserted against feudal landed property,
and, therefore, in its own way at first took on a feudal form. Certainly
the refugee serfs treated their previous servitude as something
accidental to their personality. But here they only were doing what
every class that is freeing itself from a fetter does; and they did not
free themselves as a class but separately. Moreover, they did not rise
above the system of estates, but only formed a new estate, retaining
their previous mode of labour even in their new situation, and
developing it further by freeing it from its earlier fetters, which no
longer corresponded to the development already attained.15
¶For the proletarians, on the other hand, the condition of their existence, labour, and with it all the conditions of existence governing modern society, have become something accidental, something over which they, as separate individuals, have no control, and over which no social organisation can give them control. The contradiction between the individuality of each separate proletarian and labour, the condition of life forced upon him, becomes evident to him himself, for he is sacrificed from youth upwards and, within his own class, has no chance of arriving at the conditions which would place him in the other class.
¶Thus, while the refugee serfs only wished to be free to develop and assert those conditions of existence which were already there, and hence, in the end, only arrived at free labour, the proletarians, if they are to assert themselves as individuals, will have to abolish the very condition of their existence hitherto (which has, moreover, been that of all society up to the present), namely, labour. Thus they find themselves directly opposed to the form in which, hitherto, the individuals, of which society consists, have given themselves collective expression, that is, the State. In order, therefore, to assert themselves as individuals, they must overthrow the State.
¶It follows from all we have been saying up till now that the communal relationship into which the individuals of a class entered, and which was determined by their common interests over against a third party, was always a community to which these individuals belonged only as average individuals, only insofar as they lived within the conditions of existence of their class – a relationship in which they participated not as individuals but as members of a class. With the community of revolutionary proletarians, on the other hand, who take their conditions of existence and those of all members of society under their control, it is just the reverse; it is as individuals that the individuals participate in it. It is just this combination of individuals (assuming the advanced stage of modern productive forces, of course) which puts the conditions of the free development and movement of individuals under their control – conditions which were previously abandoned to chance and had won an independent existence over against the separate individuals just because of their separation as individuals, and because of the necessity of their combination which had been determined by the division of labour, and through their separation had become a bond alien to them. Combination up till now (by no means an arbitrary one, such as is expounded for example in the Contrat social, but a necessary one) was an agreement upon these conditions, within which the individuals were free to enjoy the freaks of fortune (compare, e.g., the formation of the North American State and the South American republics). This right to the undisturbed enjoyment, within certain conditions, of fortuity and chance has up till now been called personal freedom. These conditions of existence are, of course, only the productive forces and forms of intercourse at any particular time.
§ Forms of Intercourse
¶Communism differs from all previous movements in that it overturns the basis of all earlier relations of production and intercourse, and for the first time consciously treats all natural premises as the creatures of hitherto existing men, strips them of their natural character and subjugates them to the power of the united individuals. Its organisation is, therefore, essentially economic, the material production of the conditions of this unity; it turns existing conditions into conditions of unity. The reality, which communism is creating, is precisely the true basis for rendering it impossible that anything should exist independently of individuals, insofar as reality is only a product of the preceding intercourse of individuals themselves. Thus the communists in practice treat the conditions created up to now by production and intercourse as inorganic conditions, without, however, imagining that it was the plan or the destiny of previous generations to give them material, and without believing that these conditions were inorganic for the individuals creating them.
Contradiction between individuals and their conditions of life as contradiction between productive forces and the form of intercourse
¶The difference between the individual as a person and what is accidental to him, is not a conceptual difference but an historical fact. This distinction has a different significance at different times – e.g. the estate as something accidental to the individual in the eighteenth century, the family more or less too. It is not a distinction that we have to make for each age, but one which each age makes itself from among the different elements which it finds in existence, and indeed not according to any theory, but compelled by material collisions in life.
¶What appears accidental to the later age as opposed to the earlier – and this applies also to the elements handed down by an earlier age – is a form of intercourse which corresponded to a definite stage of development of the productive forces. The relation of the productive forces to the form of intercourse is the relation of the form of intercourse to the occupation or activity of the individuals. (The fundamental form of this activity is, of course, material, on which depend all other forms – mental, political, religious, etc. The various shaping of material life is, of course, in every case dependent on the needs which are already developed, and the production, as well as the satisfaction, of these needs is an historical process, which is not found in the case of a sheep or a dog (Stirner’s refractory principal argument adversus hominem), although sheep and dogs in their present form certainly, but malgré eux, are products of an historical process.) The conditions under which individuals have intercourse with each other, so long as the above-mentioned contradiction is absent, are conditions appertaining to their individuality, in no way external to them; conditions under which these definite individuals, living under definite relationships, can alone produce their material life and what is connected with it, are thus the conditions of their self-activity and are produced by this self-activity. The definite condition under which they produce, thus corresponds, as long as the contradiction has not yet appeared, to the reality of their conditioned nature, their one-sided existence, the one-sidedness of which only becomes evident when the contradiction enters on the scene and thus exists for the later individuals. Then this condition appears as an accidental fetter, and the consciousness that it is a fetter is imputed to the earlier age as well.
¶These various conditions, which appear first as conditions of self-activity, later as fetters upon it, form in the whole evolution of history a coherent series of forms of intercourse, the coherence of which consists in this: in the place of an earlier form of intercourse, which has become a fetter, a new one is put, corresponding to the more developed productive forces and, hence, to the advanced mode of the self-activity of individuals – a form which in its turn becomes a fetter and is then replaced by another. Since these conditions correspond at every stage to the simultaneous development of the productive forces, their history is at the same time the history of the evolving productive forces taken over by each new generation, and is, therefore, the history of the development of the forces of the individuals themselves.
¶Since this evolution takes place naturally, i.e. is not subordinated to a general plan of freely combined individuals, it proceeds from various localities, tribes, nations, branches of labour, etc. each of which to start with develops independently of the others and only gradually enters into relation with the others. Furthermore, it takes place only very slowly; the various stages and interests are never completely overcome, but only subordinated to the prevailing interest and trail along beside the latter for centuries afterwards. It follows from this that within a nation itself the individuals, even apart from their pecuniary circumstances, have quite different developments, and that an earlier interest, the peculiar form of intercourse of which has already been ousted by that belonging to a later interest, remains for a long time afterwards in possession of a traditional power in the illusory community (State, law), which has won an existence independent of the individuals; a power which in the last resort can only be broken by a revolution. This explains why, with reference to individual points which allow of a more general summing-up, consciousness can sometimes appear further advanced than the contemporary empirical relationships, so that in the struggles of a later epoch one can refer to earlier theoreticians as authorities.
¶On the other hand, in countries which, like North America, begin in an already advanced historical epoch, the development proceeds very rapidly. Such countries have no other natural premises than the individuals, who settled there and were led to do so because the forms of intercourse of the old countries did not correspond to their wants. Thus they begin with the most advanced individuals of the old countries, and, therefore, with the correspondingly most advanced form of intercourse, before this form of intercourse has been able to establish itself in the old countries. This is the case with all colonies, insofar as they are not mere military or trading stations. Carthage, the Greek colonies, and Iceland in the eleventh and twelfth centuries, provide examples of this. A similar relationship issues from conquest, when a form of intercourse which has evolved on another soil is brought over complete to the conquered country: whereas in its home it was still encumbered with interests and relationships left over from earlier periods, here it can and must be established completely and without hindrance, if only to assure the conquerors’ lasting power. (England and Naples after the Norman conquest, when they received the most perfect form of feudal organisation.)
The Contradiction Between the Productive Forces and the Form of Intercourse as the Basis for Social Revolution
¶This contradiction between the productive forces and the form of intercourse, which, as we saw, has occurred several times in past history, without, however, endangering the basis, necessarily on each occasion burst out in a revolution, taking on at the same time various subsidiary forms, such as all-embracing collisions, collisions of various classes, contradiction of consciousness, battle of ideas, etc., political conflict, etc. From a narrow point of view one may isolate one of these subsidiary forms and consider it as the basis of these revolutions; and this is all the more easy as the individuals who started the revolutions had illusions about their own activity according to their degree of culture and the stage of historical development.
¶Thus all collisions in history have their origin, according to our view, in the contradiction between the productive forces and the form of intercourse. Incidentally, to lead to collisions in a country, this contradiction need not necessarily have reached its extreme limit in this particular country. The competition with industrially more advanced countries, brought about by the expansion of international intercourse, is sufficient to produce a similar contradiction in countries with a backward industry (e.g. the latent proletariat in Germany brought into view by view by the competition of English industry).
§ Conquest
¶This whole interpretation of history appears to be contradicted by the fact of conquest. Up till now violence, war, pillage, murder and robbery, etc. have been accepted as the driving force of history. Here we must limit ourselves to the chief points and take, therefore, only the most striking example – the destruction of an old civilisation by a barbarous people and the resulting formation of an entirely new organisation of society. (Rome and the barbarians; feudalism and Gaul; the Byzantine Empire and the Turks.)
¶With the conquering barbarian people war itself is still, as indicated above, a regular form of intercourse, which is the more eagerly exploited as the increase in population together with the traditional and, for it, the only possible, crude mode of production gives rise to the need for new means of production. In Italy, on the other hand, the concentration of landed property (caused not only by buying-up and indebtedness but also by inheritance, since loose living being rife and marriage rare, the old families gradually died out and their possessions fell into the hands of a few) and its conversion into grazing land (caused not only by the usual economic forces still operative today but by the importation of plundered and tribute-corn and the resultant lack of demand for Italian corn) brought about the almost total disappearance of the free population. The very slaves died out again and again, and had constantly to be replaced by new ones. Slavery remained the basis of the whole productive system. The plebeians, midway between freemen and slaves, never succeeded in becoming more than a proletarian rabble. Rome indeed never became more than a city; its connection with the provinces was almost exclusively political and could, therefore, easily be broken again by political events.
¶Nothing is more common than the notion that in history up till now it has only been a question of taking. The barbarians take the Roman Empire, and this fact of taking is made to explain the transition from the old world to the feudal system. In this taking by barbarians, however, the question is, whether the nation which is conquered has evolved industrial productive forces, as is the case with modern peoples, or whether their productive forces are based for the most part merely on their association and on the community. Taking is further determined by the object taken. A banker’s fortune, consisting of paper, cannot be taken at all, without the taker’s submitting to the conditions of production and intercourse of the country taken. Similarly the total industrial capital of a modern industrial country. And finally, everywhere there is very soon an end to taking, and when there is nothing more to take, you have to set about producing. From this necessity of producing, which very soon asserts itself, it follows that the form of community adopted by the settling conquerors must correspond to the stage of development of the productive forces they find in existence; or, if this is not the case from the start, it must change according to the productive forces. By this, too, is explained the fact, which people profess to have noticed everywhere in the period following the migration of the peoples, namely, that the servant was master, and that the conquerors very soon took over language, culture and manners from the conquered. The feudal system was by no means brought complete from Germany, but had its origin, as far as the conquerors were concerned, in the martial organisation of the army during the actual conquest, and this only evolved after the conquest into the feudal system proper through the action of the productive forces found in the conquered countries. To what an extent this form was determined by the productive forces is shown by the abortive attempts to realise other forms derived from reminiscences of ancient Rome (Charlemagne, etc.).
§ Contradictions of Big Industry: Revolution
¶Our investigation hitherto started from the instruments of production, and it has already shown that private property was a necessity for certain industrial stages. In industrie extractive private property still coincides with labour; in small industry and all agriculture up till now property is the necessary consequence of the existing instruments of production; in big industry the contradiction between the instrument of production and private property appears from the first time and is the product of big industry; moreover, big industry must be highly developed to produce this contradiction. And thus only with big industry does the abolition of private property become possible.
Contradiction Between the Productive Forces and the Form of Intercourse
¶In big industry and competition the whole mass of conditions of
existence, limitations, biases of individuals, are fused together into
the two simplest forms: private property and labour. With money every
form of intercourse, and intercourse itself, is considered fortuitous
for the individuals. Thus money implies that all previous intercourse
was only intercourse of individuals under particular conditions, not of
individuals as individuals. These conditions are reduced to two:
accumulated labour or private property, and actual labour. If both or
one of these ceases, then intercourse comes to a standstill. The modern
economists themselves, e.g. Sismondi, Cherbuliez, etc., oppose
association of individuals
to association of capital.
On
the other hand, the individuals themselves are entirely subordinated to
the division of labour and hence are brought into the most complete
dependence on one another. Private property, insofar as within labour
itself it is opposed to labour, evolves out of the necessity of
accumulation, and has still, to begin with, rather the form of the
communality; but in its further development it approaches more and more
the modern form of private property. The division of labour implies from
the outset the division of the conditions of labour, of tools and
materials, and thus the splitting-up of accumulated capital among
different owners, and thus, also, the division between capital and
labour, and the different forms of property itself. The more the
division of labour develops and accumulation grows, the sharper are the
forms that this process of differentiation assumes. Labour itself can
only exist on the premise of this fragmentation.
¶Thus two facts are here revealed. First the productive forces appear as a world for themselves, quite independent of and divorced from the individuals, alongside the individuals: the reason for this is that the individuals, whose forces they are, exist split up and in opposition to one another, whilst, on the other hand, these forces are only real forces in the intercourse and association of these individuals. Thus, on the one hand, we have a totality of productive forces, which have, as it were, taken on a material form and are for the individuals no longer the forces of the individuals but of private property, and hence of the individuals only insofar as they are owners of private property themselves. Never, in any earlier period, have the productive forces taken on a form so indifferent to the intercourse of individuals as individuals, because their intercourse itself was formerly a restricted one. On the other hand, standing over against these productive forces, we have the majority of the individuals from whom these forces have been wrested away, and who, robbed thus of all real life-content, have become abstract individuals, but who are, however, only by this fact put into a position to enter into relation with one another as individuals.
¶The only connection which still links them with the productive forces and with their own existence – labour – has lost all semblance of self-activity and only sustains their life by stunting it. While in the earlier periods self-activity and the production of material life were separated, in that they devolved on different persons, and while, on account of the narrowness of the individuals themselves, the production of material life was considered as a subordinate mode of self-activity, they now diverge to such an extent that altogether material life appears as the end, and what produces this material life, labour (which is now the only possible but, as we see, negative form of self-activity), as the means.
The Necessity, Preconditions and Consequences of the Abolition of Private Property
¶Thus things have now come to such a pass that the individuals must appropriate the existing totality of productive forces, not only to achieve self-activity, but, also, merely to safeguard their very existence. This appropriation is first determined by the object to be appropriated, the productive forces, which have been developed to a totality and which only exist within a universal intercourse. From this aspect alone, therefore, this appropriation must have a universal character corresponding to the productive forces and the intercourse.
¶The appropriation of these forces is itself nothing more than the development of the individual capacities corresponding to the material instruments of production. The appropriation of a totality of instruments of production is, for this very reason, the development of a totality of capacities in the individuals themselves.
¶This appropriation is further determined by the persons appropriating. Only the proletarians of the present day, who are completely shut off from all self-activity, are in a position to achieve a complete and no longer restricted self-activity, which consists in the appropriation of a totality of productive forces and in the thus postulated development of a totality of capacities. All earlier revolutionary appropriations were restricted; individuals, whose self-activity was restricted by a crude instrument of production and a limited intercourse, appropriated this crude instrument of production, and hence merely achieved a new state of limitation. Their instrument of production became their property, but they themselves remained subordinate to the division of labour and their own instrument of production. In all expropriations up to now, a mass of individuals remained subservient to a single instrument of production; in the appropriation by the proletarians, a mass of instruments of production must be made subject to each individual, and property to all. Modern universal intercourse can be controlled by individuals, therefore, only when controlled by all.
¶This appropriation is further determined by the manner in which it must be effected. It can only be effected through a union, which by the character of the proletariat itself can again only be a universal one, and through a revolution, in which, on the one hand, the power of the earlier mode of production and intercourse and social organisation is overthrown, and, on the other hand, there develops the universal character and the energy of the proletariat, without which the revolution cannot be accomplished; and in which, further, the proletariat rids itself of everything that still clings to it from its previous position in society.
¶Only at this stage does self-activity coincide with material life, which corresponds to the development of individuals into complete individuals and the casting-off of all natural limitations. The transformation of labour into self-activity corresponds to the transformation of the earlier limited intercourse into the intercourse of individuals as such. With the appropriation of the total productive forces through united individuals, private property comes to an end. Whilst previously in history a particular condition always appeared as accidental, now the isolation of individuals and the particular private gain of each man have themselves become accidental.
¶The individuals, who are no longer subject to the division of labour,
have been conceived by the philosophers as an ideal, under the name
Man
. They have conceived the whole process which we have outlined
as the evolutionary process of Man,
so that at every historical
stage Man
was substituted for the individuals and shown as the
motive force of history. The whole process was thus conceived as a
process of the self-estrangement of Man,
and this was essentially
due to the fact that the average individual of the later stage was
always foisted on to the earlier stage, and the consciousness of a later
age on to the individuals of an earlier. Through this inversion, which
from the first is an abstract image of the actual conditions, it was
possible to transform the whole of history into an evolutionary process
of consciousness.
§ The Necessity of the Communist Revolution
¶Finally, from the conception of history we have sketched we obtain these further conclusions:
- In the development of productive forces there comes a stage when productive forces and means of intercourse are brought into being, which, under the existing relationships, only cause mischief, and are no longer productive but destructive forces (machinery and money); and connected with this a class is called forth, which has to bear all the burdens of society without enjoying its advantages, which, ousted from society, is forced into the most decided antagonism to all other classes; a class which forms the majority of all members of society, and from which emanates the consciousness of the necessity of a fundamental revolution, the communist consciousness, which may, of course, arise among the other classes too through the contemplation of the situation of this class.
- The conditions under which definite productive forces can be applied are the conditions of the rule of a definite class of society, whose social power, deriving from its property, has its practical-idealistic expression in each case in the form of the State; and, therefore, every revolutionary struggle is directed against a class, which till then has been in power.16
- In all revolutions up till now the mode of activity always remained unscathed and it was only a question of a different distribution of this activity, a new distribution of labour to other persons, whilst the communist revolution is directed against the preceding mode of activity, does away with labour, and abolishes the rule of all classes with the classes themselves, because it is carried through by the class which no longer counts as a class in society, is not recognised as a class, and is in itself the expression of the dissolution of all classes, nationalities, etc. within present society; and
- Both for the production on a mass scale of this communist consciousness, and for the success of the cause itself, the alteration of men on a mass scale is, necessary, an alteration which can only take place in a practical movement, a revolution; this revolution is necessary, therefore, not only because the ruling class cannot be overthrown in any other way, but also because the class overthrowing it can only in a revolution succeed in ridding itself of all the muck of ages and become fitted to found society anew.
The building of houses. With savages each family has as a matter of course its own cave or hut like the separate family tent of the nomads. This separate domestic economy is made only the more necessary by the further development of private property. With the agricultural peoples a communal domestic economy is just as impossible as a communal cultivation of the soil. A great advance was the building of towns. In all previous periods, however, the abolition of individual economy, which is inseparable from the abolition of private property, was impossible for the simple reason that the material conditions governing it were not present. The setting-up of a communal domestic economy presupposes the development of machinery, of the use of natural forces and of many other productive forces – e.g. of water-supplies, of gas-lighting, steam-heating, etc., the removal [of the antagonism] of town and country. Without these conditions a communal economy would not in itself form a new productive force; lacking any material basis and resting on a purely theoretical foundation, it would be a mere freak and would end in nothing more than a monastic economy – What was possible can be seen in the towns brought about by condensation and the erection of communal buildings for various definite purposes (prisons, barracks, etc.). That the abolition of individual economy is inseparable from the abolition of the family is self-evident↩︎
And out of this very contradiction between the interest of the individual and that of the community the latter takes an independent form as the State, divorced from the real interests of individual and community, and at the same time as an illusory communal life, always based, however, on the real ties existing in every family and tribal conglomeration – such as flesh and blood, language, division of labour on a larger scale, and other interests – and especially, as we shall enlarge upon later, on the classes, already determined by the division of labour, which in every such mass of men separate out, and of which one dominates all the others. It follows from this that all struggles within the State, the struggle between democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy, the struggle for the franchise, etc., etc., are merely the illusory forms in which the real struggles of the different classes are fought out among one another (of this the German theoreticians have not the faintest inkling, although they have received a sufficient introduction to the subject in the Deutsch-Französische Jahrbücher and Die heilige Familie). Further, it follows that every class which is struggling for mastery, even when its domination, as is the case with the proletariat, postulates the abolition of the old form of society in its entirety and of domination itself, must first conquer for itself political power in order to represent its interest in turn as the general interest, which in the first moment it is forced to do. Just because individuals seek only their particular interest, which for them does not coincide with their communal interest (in fact the general is the illusory form of communal life), the latter will be imposed on them as an interest
alien
to them, andindependent
of them as in its turn a particular, peculiargeneral
interest; or they themselves must remain within this discord, as in democracy. On the other hand, too, the practical struggle of these particular interests, which constantly really run counter to the communal and illusory communal interests, makes practical intervention and control necessary through the illusorygeneral
interest in the form of the State.↩︎An allusion to a type of light literature which was widely read at the end of the 18th and the beginning of the 19th century; many of its characters were knights, robbers and ghosts, e.g., Abällino, der grosse Bandit by Heinrich Daniel Zschokke published in 1793, and Rinaldo Rinaldini, der Räuberhauptmann by Christian August Vulpius (1797).↩︎
Rhine-song (
Der deutsche Rhein
) – a poem by Nicolaus Becker which was widely used by nationalists in their own interest. It was written in 1840 and set to music by several composers.↩︎This section formed originally part of Chapter III and followed directly after the passage to which Marx and Engels refer here↩︎
Four pages of the manuscript are missing here. - Ed.↩︎
Navigation Laws – a series of Acts passed in England from 1381 onwards to protect English shipping against foreign companies. The Navigation Laws were modified in the early nineteenth century and repealed in 1849 except for a reservation regarding coasting trade, which was revoked in 1854.↩︎
The movement of capital, although considerably accelerated, still remained, however, relatively slow. The splitting-up of the world market into separate parts, each of which was exploited by a particular nation, the exclusion of competition among themselves on the part of the nations, the clumsiness of production itself and the fact that finance was only evolving from its early stages, greatly impeded circulation. The consequence of this was a haggling, mean and niggardly spirit which still clung to all merchants and to the whole mode of carrying on trade. Compared with the manufacturers, and above all with the craftsmen, they were certainly big bourgeois; compared with the merchants and industrialists of the next period they remain petty bourgeois. Cf. Adam Smith.↩︎
Competition separates individuals from one another, not only the bourgeois but still more the workers, in spite of the fact that it brings them together. Hence it is a long time before these individuals can unite, apart from the fact that for the purposes of this union – if it is not to be merely local – the necessary means, the great industrial cities and cheap and quick communications, have first to be produced by big industry. Hence every organised power standing over against these isolated individuals, who live in relationships, daily reproducing this isolation, can only be overcome after long struggles. To demand the opposite would be tantamount to demanding that competition should not exist in this definite epoch of history, or that the individuals should banish from their minds relationships over which in their isolation they have no control.↩︎
Ownership in accordance with the law applying to full Roman citizens. - Ed.↩︎
The right of using and consuming (also: abusing), i.e. of disposing of a thing at will.↩︎
Notes, written by Marx, intended for further elaboration↩︎
To begin with it absorbs the branches of labour directly belonging to the State and then all [more or less] ideological estates.↩︎
The Statement which frequently occurs with Saint Max that each is all that he is through the State is fundamentally the same as the statement that bourgeois is only a specimen of the bourgeois species; a statement which presupposes that the class of bourgeois existed before the individuals constituting it. [Marginal note by Marx to this sentence:] With the philosophers pre-existence of the class.↩︎
N.B. – It must not be forgotten that the serf’s very need of existing and the impossibility of a large-scale economy, which involved the distribution of the allotments among the serfs, very soon reduced the services of the serfs to their lord to an average of payments in kind and statute-labour. This made it possible for the serf to accumulate movable property and hence facilitated his escape out of the possession of his lord and gave him the prospect of making his way as an urban citizen; it also created gradations among the serfs, so that the runaway serfs were already half burghers. It is likewise obvious that the serfs who were masters of a craft had the best chance of acquiring movable property.↩︎
[Marginal note by Marx:] The people are interested in maintaining the present state of production.↩︎