§ Preface
¶Here’s an old Wildcat text, and the little covering note added when
it was posted to intsdiscnet last year. (It created quite a stir.) This
text was written by a Wildcat member for a conference held in London in
1988. It was criticised quite heavily, not least by other Wildcat
members, in particular for its attacks on Marx’s method. Nonetheless,
the basic argument, that the theories of imperialism are not useful to
communist and should be abandoned, expressed a commonly
held
position.
§ Introduction
¶This essay suffers from the usual problems caused by Wildcat’s lack of resources. There are some missing components, and it needs some editing. In spite of these, it is an important contribution to the necessary theoretical work of the communist movement. It was originally intended as a discussion of the problem of imperialism. However as the essay explains, in the course of writing it I became convinced that imperialism is a red herring. Instead it discusses the real issue, Nations and Nationalism. In passing it glosses over other important issues such as decadence and the Marxist Method. The purpose of this essay and the meeting it was written for is to contribute to a discussion about an international Platform to form the theoretical basis of a regroupment of revolutionaries with the aim of assisting the centralisation of the international class struggle.
§ Marx and Engels
¶Marx and Engels had little to say on the subject of imperialism.
Their remarks on colonialism and foreign trade, particularly the section
on counter-tendencies to the tendency of the falling rate of profit, in
Capital 31 have been well explained by their
epigones, and used to give authority to their own investigations. Their
20th century successors have been in a better position to shed light on
the developments which led to August 1914, so I concentrate on them in
the next section. More significant are Marx and Engel’s views on Method,
which underlie much subsequent work. The errors of Lenin, for example,
cannot always be conveniently explained away as a departure from the
Method of Marx. We don’t want to get Marx off the hook. Before calling
ourselves Marxists
we need to work out how much of Marx and
Engels’ method or methods we should adopt. In The German
Ideology (1846) Marx polemicised against his Hegelian classmates
and outlined the materialist conception of history. The premises from
which we begin are not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real premises
from which abstraction can only be made in the imagination. They are the
real individuals, their activity and the material conditions under which
they live, both those which they find already existing and those
produced by their activity. These premises can thus be verified in a
purely empirical way
.2
¶But Marx’s ideas are often very difficult if not impossible to verify
in this way. Take the following extracts from the Preface to A
Critique of Political Economy. At a certain stage of their
development, the material productive forces of society come into
conflict with the existing relations of production, or – what is but a
legal expression for the same thing – with the property relations within
which they have been at work hitherto. From forms of the development of
the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. … new,
higher relations of production never appear before the material
conditions of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society itself. Therefore mankind always sets itself only such tasks as
it can solve
.3 See also Engels, The Dialectics
of Nature.
¶In 1846, Marx seemed to be breaking with Hegelian ideology. But
throughout the rest of his work, the ghost of dialectics seemed to keep
whispering in his ear. It is unfortunate that Marx died before the
philosophical routing of Hegel which took place in England at the
beginning of the 20th Century. The above passage from the
Preface shows well the elegant seductiveness of dialectical
thought. We should be as wary of it as we are of modern physicists who
claim their theories must be true because they are elegant. Look where
dialectical reasoning led Marx. The statement that mankind only sets
itself such problems as it can solve is patently false. The problem of
travelling to distant galaxies in a short time has been set, but cannot
be solved. And there is no empirical evidence for the view that history
proceeds according to a pattern of forms and fetters. Relations
and forces
of production are arbitrary abstract categories. As we
see in the subsequent section, dialectical thought helped lead Marx’s
disciples astray.
… And Their Followers.
¶The more radical elements within the Second International had good
organisational and political reasons to see themselves as the successors
of Marx and Engels. Around the turn of the century, various debates took
place among these radical social democrats about imperialism and
nationalism. The most famous of these is Lenin. This is a pity. Lenin
argued that imperialism was in part a conscious strategy to buy off the
working classes in the Imperialist countries. His evidence is one quote
from Cecil Rhodes.4 From Rhodes’s opinion that
imperialism would help avoid revolution in Britain, Lenin derived his
theory of the Labour Aristocracy, which shows his moralism at its
crudest. But he also quotes Engels to the effect that the workers of
England merrily share the feast
of England’s colonies. He
condemns the economic parasitism
by means of which the English
ruling class bribe the lower classes into acquiescence
. What
infantile, petit-bourgeois rubbish! The ruling class in all countries
pay workers as much as they think they have to, calculated from (a) the
need for workers to stay alive and, to a greater or lesser extent,
healthy, (b) the shortage or otherwise of workers capable of doing the
job, and (c) the class struggle. Where does a wage rise gained by
struggle end and a bribe begin? How can British workers deduce what
proportion of their wage packets are the proceeds of the exploitation of
the colonies, and should they hand that proportion back to their
employers, declaring their refusal to be bribed? In reality, if you
accept the idea of dividing the working class up into more or less
exploited sections, it is not necessarily true that As far as capital
invested in the colonies, etc. is concerned, however, the reason why
this can yield higher rates of profit is that the profit rate is
generally higher there on account of the lower degree of development,
and so too is the exploitation of labour, through the use of slaves and
coolies, etc.
.5
¶In reality, workers in the advanced
countries often produce
more profit as a proportion of their wages than those in backward
countries. Lenin bases his views on off-hand remarks by Marx and Engels
and ignores the better worked-out passages which can be used to develop
an analysis of the world economy without the concept of imperialism (see
for example6). We need waste no more time on
Lenin.
¶Bukharin is more difficult. Though he supports Lenin’s theory of the Labour Aristocracy, he does have a deeper understanding of the more serious aspects of Marx’s ideas. In fact he has a dialectical approach, claiming to see a contradiction between nation states and international capitalism.7
¶Capitalism has created the world economy, the basis of communism, but
national economies
and state capitalist trusts
contradict
this, leading to imperialism and war. Imperialism was written
in 1915, and his desire to show that imperialism is inevitable is
obviously the result of the war, and his rejection of the possibility of
a reformist solution to it. The reason he has to show a dialectical
contradiction between nations and the world economy is in order to
reject the theory of ultra-imperialism, which held that capitalism could
gradually evolve into One Big Company, abolishing war. But his rejection
is clumsy. The development of world capitalism leads, on the one
hand, to an internationalisation of economic life, and, on the other, to
the levelling of economic differences, – and, to an infinitely greater
degree, the same process of economic development intensifies the
tendency to
nationalise” capitalist interests, to form narrow
national
groups armed to the teeth and ready to hurl themselves
at one another at any moment”.8 This is because, he
says, state capitalism is the capitalism of existing, national states.
Though the economy is increasingly international, Acquisition,
however, assumes the character of
.9 Considering how central it is to his
theory, he is obliged to explain what he means by national
(state) acquisition
where the beneficiaries are huge state companies of the bourgeoisie of
finance capitalnational
, which
he puts in inverted commas throughout the book. The reason he does so is
clear from the footnote on p. 80 which is the only place he attempts to
explain his crucial concept. When we speak of
What is also clear is
that he has only the haziest notion of what national capitals are. This
undermines his theory rather seriously. Bukharin assumes that capital is
divided into particular national
capital, national
economy, we have in mind here as elsewhere, not
the element of nationality in the strict sense of the word, but the
territorial state conception of economic life.narrow
when this
is what he has to prove in order to refute ultra-imperialism. He
underestimates capitalism’s flexibility, its knack of continually
revolutionising the productive forces. Is there any reason why single
capitalist firms should be tied to one state? Is it impossible for
capital to dissolve particular national states and replace them with
larger entities, such as the European Community? Is there any limit to
the size of such entities? Bukharin answers yes, but doesn’t explain
why.national
groups
¶Luxemburg’s most important contribution to the debate on imperialism
was her opposition to the idea that imperialism could be opposed by
supporting national liberation movements. On the contrary, she argued,
imperialism tends to make national liberation reactionary and
impossible. Her empirical observations of the effects of Polish national
liberation movements on the class struggle in the Russian Empire expose
a chink in Marx’s armour. In Foreword to the Anthology
(1905) she
argues against support for these movements.10
She fearlessly attacked Marx for supporting Polish nationalism until his
death, and accuses him of mechanically applying his own theory! If Marx
can’t use his own method correctly, what chance have we? She shows he
was wrong by looking at the facts of Poland’s integration into the
Russian Empire, tending to unite the working class of Russia and Poland,
and of how Polish nationalism acted against that unity during the
revolution of 1905. Luxemburg rejects eternal truths
like support
for national liberation in favour of an empirical, case-by-case
approach, and claims this is the Marxist method. So far from deducing
that national liberation has always been anti-proletarian, she claims
that there was a case for supporting certain liberation movements in the
19th century. Luxemburg’s arguments were seriously debated at the time,
and many social democrats, including a significant section of the
Bolsheviks, supported her views against Lenin’s right of nations to
self-determination
. Eventually Lenin’s views won the day, and the
Communist International supported national liberation movements and thus
the massacre of the proletariat in China, Germany, etc. etc.. The most
obvious reason for Lenin’s success was the power of the Soviet Union.
Another reason for the weakness of opposition to Lenin’s petit-bourgeois
liberal position was the inability of his opponents to break from
liberal democratic aspects of the Marxist tradition. Marxists, Marx and
Engels included, have tended to argue that the bourgeoisie betray
the ideals of their own revolution. At the other end of the scale, we
are familiar with the beliefs of certain ex-members of Wildcat that the
bourgeoisie aren’t really democratic. Many of the weaknesses of
Luxemburg’s positions derive from this type of error. She defends the
proletariat as the true defender of democracy against Absolutism, and
even as the bearer of Western Civilisation against Czarist barbarism. We
know where this position led, but we sometimes like to forget who
invented it. The bourgeoisie did not betray the revolutions of the 19th
century. It simply defended its class interests against the proletariat,
and used it as cannon fodder against inconvenient historical entities.
An examination of Marx and Engels’s own accounts of the bourgeois
movements of the 19th century shows they were wrong to support them.
This is not an eternal truth
, but it’s at least 200 years old.
Democracy leads Luxemburg to make major concessions to the idea of
national self-determination, arguing that the working class constitutes
the majority
of the nation. Rather than simply showing
nationalism is the enemy of the working class, period, she claims the
bourgeoisie distorts or makes meaningless the idea of nationalism. This
leads to the weakest but most famous of her arguments against Lenin –
national liberation is impossible because of the domination of the
planet by imperialism.11 We reject nationalism as
anti-working class not because the bourgeoisie betrays it, not because
it’s impossible, but because it ties the proletariat to its class enemy
and divides it amongst itself. Luxemburg does not start from an
internationalist position, but from a longing for the harmony of
interests of all nationalities
as the national policy of the
proletariat
.12 She assumes that nations are real.
However, she could claim Marx as a progenitor even whilst arguing with
some of his conclusions. The idea of progress, the idea the proletariat
should support the revolutionary bourgeois smashing of old feudal
fetters, and its democratic corollary, were defended by Marx better than
anyone. We must rescue these ideas from the gnawing criticism of the
mice and give them to the cat.
§ What Is Imperialism?
¶In this section, I briefly go through some of the most important definitions of imperialism to see whether any of them are any use to our analysis of the modern capitalist world.
§ Imperialism = Empires
¶This nominalist understanding of imperialism is clearly useless, since it makes nations with clearly defined Empires like the USSR more imperialist than those with few formally-defined colonies like the USA. It would make Portugal imperialist until 1974 but not Spain. Obviously, if we accept the bourgeois picture of the world divided into nations, we can easily see that some nations dominate others by means other that crude military colonialism.
§ Nations tend to dominate others
¶Again assuming the reality of nation states (though unlike Bukharin,
I examine this assumption in depth in subsequent sections), even making
this assumption, this definition is no use either. Almost every country
is more powerful than others, and tries to dominate them. Russia tends
to dominate Vietnam, which tends to dominate Kampuchea. India,
apparently ignorant of Marx’s advice that a nation which rules another
can never itself be free, leans very heavily on Bhutan, Sikkim, Nepal,
Bangladesh, Sri Lanka and the Maldives, and would do so on Pakistan were
not the latter dominated by the USA. Even the smallest countries harbour
imperialist designs on their neighbours, e.g. Albania wouldn’t mind
Kosovo, currently in Yugoslavia. Nations tend to dominate others
leads to the view that nearly all countries are imperialist, and is
therefore no good.
International Capitalism in the Epoch of Decadence
¶Defining imperialism as international capitalism also lacks utility.
When the left communist paper Teachers Voice called for
Imperialism Out of the Gulf
, it didn’t mean International
Capitalism out of the Gulf. It meant a specific policy of a specific
section of world capital, or to put it another way Yankee Go
Home
. Imperialism is only useful as a definition if it means a
specific type of capitalism. If this is worth fighting more than humdrum
ordinary capitalism (i.e. more than just waging a permanent and total
war against) then we will have found a useful definition. The only
possibility for defining imperialism as international capitalism is to
use it as a synonym for capitalist decadence. This theory depends on
Marx’s teleological view of history as a succession of stages, of modes
of production each giving birth to its successor, each having a given
historical task
. We can either accept or reject the idea of
refutation as a criterion of meaning – the idea that a statement is
meaningful if you can say how to prove or disprove it. If we reject it,
on what grounds could we accept or reject Marx’s teleology? Why not, for
example, accept the Roman paradigm of history instead? The Ancient
Romans were quite convinced that history was a series of increasingly
degenerate stages. But if we accept refutation, how could we refute or
verify Marx’s vision of history? It’s difficult to reconcile decadence
with the materialist conception as defined in The German
Ideology (see section 1). The most coherent argument for decadence
derives from the view that capitalism created the world economy and thus
completed its historic task. But this is difficult to measure.
Capitalism is still increasing its domination of the world. Pannekoek
used the theory of decadence to excuse his participation in
Parliamentary Social Democracy up till 1914. This illustrates one of the
major problems with decadence – if you get the date of capitalist
decadence slightly too late, you could end up supporting one faction of
the bourgeoisie against another. Decadence was of little use to
Pannekoek and the German and Dutch Left in any case – they supported
national struggles until after world war two. How to tell if your mode
of production is Decadent. Easy – just look at the relations of
production. Are they forms for the development of the forces of
production, or fetters on that development? If the latter, your mode of
production is decadent. It’s as easy as that! Capitalism develops the
proletariat, among other things. It might be argued that its worth
supporting at certain stages for this reason. But a proletariat capable
of supporting capitalism in order to further develop the proletariat
would be conscious enough to overthrow capitalism and abolish itself.
Capitalism develops the productive forces anyway, without conscious
proletarian support. Old dynasties did not need to be overthrown by the
bourgeoisie in order to develop the productive forces – they just became
bourgeois themselves. Japan is a shining example. There may have been a
time when it was in the proletariat’s interest to support the
bourgeoisie. This is a subject for empirical research. It was certainly
before the French Revolution of 1789. No bourgeois struggles since have
been worth supporting. Marx’s dialectical mumbo-jumbo was a cover-up for
Victorian Progress ideology. The theory of decadence is an attempt to
incorporate Marx’s mistakes into the communist platform. We don’t want
them in ours.
§ The Ideology of Imperialism
¶At the end of the last century, some of the rulers of some of the
most powerful capitalist states consciously decided to try to tie their
working classes to the class enemy by means of the ideology of
imperialism. The conquest of Africa and Asia by the mother country was
supposed to turn the proles into more acquiescent subjects, particularly
if they felt they had material interests in colonialism. This ideology
has been effective. British and French workers, for example, have been
fairly saturated in the ideas of imperialism for a century or so, and
this has helped the bourgeoisie get them to die by the million for
their
respective nation states, and suppress the possibility of
revolution. The Falklands war was a sobering reminder of how easy it is
for the bourgeoisie to whip up patriotism among the masses of the
imperialist heartlands. But pernicious and effective though it may be,
it has been no more so than any other form of nationalism. For example,
anti-imperialism, the belief of workers in the struggle of oppressed
nations, greatly helped the Vietnamese bourgeoisie invade Kampuchea
after the Vietnam war. Whereas the American working class, according to
the Leninist mythology dupes of Imperialist ideology, have still not
accepted the idea of fighting another war after their resistance helped
end the one in Vietnam. Imperialist ideology is no worse than any other
nationalist ideology. A clear illustration of the irrelevance of the
distinction between imperialism, anti-imperialism, and nationalism, is
the case of Germany.
¶As Socialist Workers Party hack Chris Harman admits in his history of the German Revolution, the Comintern supported Nazis as a national liberation, anti-imperialist struggle in the oppressed nation of Germany in the 20’s. It was occupied and oppressed by French and British imperialism. Cominternists and National Socialists fought imperialism side by side. Within a decade, this anti-imperialism had become German imperialism. Thus the ideology of imperialism is useless to us, if not to the bourgeoisie. In a published text or platform, this section would be expanded to discuss the legacy of anti-imperialism, showing how it has been used by the international bourgeoisie to suppress the class struggle in countries from Argentina to Algeria, Zimbabwe and Zaire. However this is hardly necessary in a meeting of communists. I would briefly mention here that I would also go on to say anti-imperialism is fraying at the edges, mainly because you can’t eat national liberation. The first example I know where a conscious rejection of a particular nationalist ideology has taken place is recently in Algeria. Rioters explicitly identified with the intifada of Palestinian proletarians against the Zionist state. This is not far from seeing the Arab nationalist bourgeoisie and the Zionists as the same enemy. No wonder Arafat has been buzzing around the capitals of the Middle East recently.
§ Hilferding’s Definition of Imperialism
¶The policy of finance capital pursues a threefold aim: first, the
creation of the largest possible economic territory which, secondly,
must be protected against foreign competition by tariff walls, and thus,
thirdly, must become an area of exploitation for the national monopoly
companies
.13 Hilferding’s definition, on which
most of his successors depended, depends on the concept of nation
states. Rather than seeing capital moving around the world in search of
profits, he defines imperialism in terms of national monopolies
exporting capital and commodities. Nations are more basic than capital.
But imperialism was not always carried out by nations: India
and
the colony which became Indonesia were founded by companies. But I am
jumping ahead of the argument. As we saw with Bukharin, nations are hard
to define. He hurriedly offers the territorial state conception of
economic life
.14 Does he mean that nations are
whatever the bourgeoisie think they are, and they make wars on the basis
of their conceptions
? Nation states start wars, and Hilferding’s
definition can only be understood as the policy of states, particular
coalitions of capitalist groups with sovereignty (the monopoly of armed
force) over a particular acreage of the earth’s surface. I am not going
to deny that these coalitions exist. But I am going to address the
question of how fundamental these particular formations are, as opposed
to others. Is the bourgeoisie split into national sections above all
others? Unless they are, the above definition of imperialism, though by
far the best, is as non-functional as all the others.
§ The Internationalist Approach
¶There is a widespread assumption among Marxists that capitalist organisation is based on the nation state. The feudal world had no conception of nations because it was ruled by a global religious hierarchy which had no intrinsic territorial limitations. The ruling classes of the ancien regimes had no nationality – neither the Pope, nor the Bourbons, nor the Hapsburgs. These interrelated divinely appointed rulers did not belong to particular bits of the world. England has not had English monarchs since the 11th century.
¶The emergence of nations is explained by B. Anderson in Imagined
Communities as the result of three main factors.15
One is the collapse of religion. According to Anderson, the existential
angst caused by the decline of religion partly explains the rise of
nationalism as a substitute community. The destruction of communities in
general by capitalism partly explains nationalism. Capital replaces
various kinds of community with its own invention, the national
community. Another major factor is the print industry. The Latin market
became saturated, and it was economical for printers to create fairly
large reading groups based on fusing numerous dialects together into
languages: English, German, French. Luther’s translations of the early
16th century did more to create the German nation
than all the
politicians who succeeded him put together. But the most interesting
factor noted by Anderson is the conscious creation of nationalisms by
the ruling class. Pre-national dynasts deliberately promoted
nationalism. Anderson gives plenty of empirical examples to support his
argument – the Romanovs, the Hapsburgs, Chulalongkorn – all promoted
official nationalism
to preserve their power over labour and
other classes. Nineteenth century nationalisms became models. Since
1918, these models have been adapted by bourgeois students from around
the world at European Universities, and taken home
to create
nations. This has led to the creation of some rather arbitrary nations.
Anderson points out that Indonesia does not remotely correspond to
any precolonial domain
, and goes on to describe its enormous variety
of peoples, cultures, languages and religions, how the people at one end
have far more in common with their neighbours across the national
frontier than with their fellow Indonesians
, and how its shape is
determined by the last Dutch conquests.16
¶The bourgeoisie is a global class. Nations did not emerge before
capitalism. There were bourgeois before capitalism in every part of the
world. Consciously or not (and there are numerous examples of conscious
conspiracy), capitalism created nations. This suggests, though does not
prove, that they are not essential to capitalism. Some nations are less
arbitrary than others. The shape of Chile, for example, is the result of
communication lines in the various provinces of the Spanish Empire. But
the current nations of Latin America emerged after several attempts to
create larger ones. Uniquely among the authors mentioned in this
article, Anderson asks the right question: What are nations, and where
do they come from? Bukharin, following Marx and Hilferding, assumes
their reality, thus the world division of labour
between them,
and is thus able to invent the myth of imperialism. Partly a spontaneous
false community caused by the decline of other communities (though
unlike religion, Bash the Argies
does not express the heart of a
heartless world), partly the result of the linguistic centralisations
brought about by the emergence of the mass production of vernacular
(non-Latin) books in the 16th and 17th centuries, and partly as the
result of conscious decisions by a) the old non-national dynasties, and
b) the modern international bourgeois intelligentsia, Nationalism is
not the awakening of nations to self-consciousness: it invents nations
where they do not exist
.17 Anderson starts by
showing that nations are imagined communities (we tend to think we have
something in common with our fellow-nationals, most of whom we will
never meet), and then tries to work out how they were created and by
whom. The consequences can be summarised thus: The Bosses Have no
Country. If nations are imaginary, and the bosses have no country, does
it follow that the national divisions of the world and their disputes,
including massive wars and the nuclear stockpile, are all the result of
a massive conspiracy? Do the international capitalist class stage wars
in order to attack the class struggle, devalue capital, and all the time
know they are united against us? Do they approach world wars in the same
way as a game of cricket? The question is not – do the bourgeoisie think
they are divided into nations? But to some extent, we would expect their
consciousness to bear some relation to the reality if nations really are
fictions. There are examples of international conspiracies which reveal
inter-bourgeois faction fights which are not national fights. There is
the House of Windsor-Hitler collaboration prior to World War Two. There
was in all likelihood some collaboration between the various
bourgeoisies
during the war. Surely Hess did not fly to Britain
off his own bat? On the other hand, the Allies hung some of the top
Nazis after the war, though this is exceptional. Our approach does not
depend on the bourgeoisie’s consciousness of its own international
interests. Some are more conscious than others. George V and Jacques
Delors are more internationalist than Galtieri. Whether or not Galtieri
knew he was acting in the interests of British and international capital
by attacking the Falkland Islands, this is the reality. The best
examples of Machiavellian nationalism are in Russia. The Romanovs
decided they were Russian nationalists out of conscious choice. Stalin
introduced Russian nationalism back into the Soviet Union in order to
attack the class struggle and win the war. Stalin was an
internationalist who consciously promoted nationalism because it was in
the interests of capitalism. Why should we think most of the world
bourgeoisie are any less Machiavellian?
¶But whatever their origins, nations have a certain solidity. State
capitalist trusts do exist. There is a faction of the international
bourgeoisie coalesced around the Brush state. This trust
is more
solid than a company like IBM. IBM managers can leave and form new
companies or join them. Thatcher can hardly become Prime Minister of
another country. But alongside this solidity, there is considerable
flexibility. The EC is emerging slowly but surely as a new capitalist
entity, more powerful than any of its component nations. When Anderson
asks rhetorically would anyone die willingly for Comecon or the
EEC?
he implies that only the nation can inspire the
self-sacrificing stupidity that capitalism demands. But people died for
the Soviet Union before it officially turned itself into a nation, and
some probably died in Afghanistan for Comecon, under the name
socialist fraternity of nations.
We should not be complacent
about the emergence of EC-ism. If people can die for the rights of the
Falkland Islanders to remain British, they’ll swallow anything. The
bourgeoisie are organised into all kinds of supra-national entities. The
Guardian recently had nightmares trying to work out what
nation
ConsGold belonged to – Britain or South Africa? (See
diagram on following page). Like other capitalist entities, nations have
a certain reality. But inter-bourgeois faction fights can be more
important than nations, and the bourgeoisie’s common interest against
our struggle is always more so.
§ Consequences
¶Capitalism is not a contradiction between a socialised international economy and national forms which contradict it. It can abolish this contradiction. Our aim is not to free the productive forces from their fetters, but to destroy them and build communism. For this reason, we should reject the theory of decadence and significant aspects of Marx’s method which underlie it, though leaving open the question of whether there was ever the possibility of a joint struggle between capitalists and workers prior to the French Revolution, until further empirical evidence emerges. Imperialism is a non-issue. National states exist, and have a certain importance among coalitions of bourgeois interest groups against each other and against the proletariat, but nations did not predate capitalism, are not essential to it, and were created, and can be abolished by, capital. Other entities may be more important capitalist coalitions in the future. Machiavellianism is an important feature of the way the bourgeoisie operates. Having thrown various bogies into the waste disposal unit of history nations, progress, decadence and imperialism, we are left with only one fundamental contradiction the invariant class antagonisms between international labour and international capital. This must remain our reference point in our analysis of the changing world around us.
¶RB.
¶London, 25 11 88.
Economic Foundations of Capitalist Decadence. CWO London 1985. p. 15.↩︎
Selected Writings. Karl Marx. ed. D. McLellan, OUP 1977. p. 160.↩︎
Selected Writings. Karl Marx. ed. D. McLellan, OUP 1977. pp. 389-390↩︎
Imperialism, the Highest Stage of Capitalism. V.I. Lenin. Peking 1973. p. 93.↩︎
Capital, Volume 3. Karl Marx. Penguin Books 1981. p. 345.↩︎
Development and Underdevelopment. G. Kay. MacMillan 1975.↩︎
Imperialism and World Economy. N. Bukharin. Merlin, London 1976.↩︎
Imperialism and World Economy. N. Bukharin. Merlin, London 1976. pp. 106-107.↩︎
Imperialism and World Economy. N. Bukharin. Merlin, London 1976. p. 106.↩︎
The National Question. R. Luxemburg. Monthly Review Press 1977. p. 95.↩︎
The National Question and Autonomy,
in The National Question. R. Luxemburg. Monthly Review Press 1977. pp. 130-131.↩︎The National Question. R. Luxemburg. Monthly Review Press 1977. p. 168.↩︎
Hilferding, Finance Capital, cited in N. Bukharin, Imperialism and World Economy, p. 107.↩︎
Imperialism and World Economy. N. Bukharin. Merlin, London 1976. p. 80.↩︎
Imagined Communities. B. Anderson. Verso London 1983.↩︎
Imagined Communities, p. 110.↩︎
Gellner, Thought and Change, cited in B. Anderson, Imagined Communities, p. 15.↩︎