¶The everyday practical activity of tribesmen reproduces, or
perpetuates, a tribe. This reproduction is not merely physical, but
social as well. Through their daily activities the tribesmen do not
merely reproduce a group of human beings; they reproduce a tribe, namely
a particular social form within which this group of human
beings performs specific activities in a specific
manner. The specific activities of the tribesmen are not the outcome of
natural
characteristics of the men who perform them, the way the
production of honey is an outcome of the nature
of a bee. The
daily life enacted and perpetuated by the tribesman is a specific
social response to particular material and historical
conditions.
¶The everyday activity of slaves reproduces slavery. Through their daily activities, slaves do not merely reproduce themselves and their masters physically; they also reproduce the instruments with which the master represses them, and their own habits of submission to the master’s authority. To men who live in a slave society, the master-slave relation seems like a natural and eternal relation. However, men are not born masters or slaves. Slavery is a specific social form, and men submit to it only in very particular material and historical conditions.
¶The practical everyday activity of wage-workers reproduces wage labor
and capital. Through their daily activities, modern
men, like
tribesmen and slaves, reproduce the inhabitants, the social relations
and the ideas of their society; they reproduce the social form
of daily life. Like the tribe and the slave system, the capitalist
system is neither the natural nor the final form of human society; like
the earlier social forms, capitalism is a specific response to material
and historical conditions.
¶Unlike earlier forms of social activity, everyday life in capitalist society systematically transforms the material conditions to which capitalism originally responded. Some of the material limits to human activity come gradually under human control. At a high level of industrialization, practical activity creates its own material conditions as well as its social form. Thus the subject of analysis is not only how practical activity in capitalist society reproduces capitalist society, but also how this activity itself eliminates the material conditions to which capitalism is a response.
§ Daily Life in Capitalist Society
¶The social form of people’s regular activities under capitalism is a
response to a certain material and historical situation. The material
and historical conditions explain the origin of the capitalist form, but
do not explain why this form continues after the initial situation
disappears. A concept of cultural lag
is not an explanation of
the continuity of a social form after the disappearance of the initial
conditions to which it responded. This concept is merely a name for the
continuity of the social form. When the concept of cultural lag
parades as a name for a social force
which determines human
activity, it is an obfuscation which presents the outcome of people’s
activities as an external force beyond their control. This is not only
true of a concept like cultural lag.
Many of the terms used by
Marx to describe people’s activities have been raised to the status of
external and even natural
forces which determine people’s
activity; thus concepts like class struggle,
production
relations
and particularly The Dialectic,
play the same role
in the theories of some Marxists
that Original Sin,
Fate
and The Hand of Destiny
played in the theories of
medieval mystifiers.
¶In the performance of their daily activities, the members of capitalist society simultaneously carry out two processes: they reproduce the form of their activities, and they eliminate the material conditions to which this form of activity initially responded. But they do not know they carry out these processes; their own activities are not transparent to them. They are under the illusion that their activities are responses to natural conditions beyond their control and do not see that they are themselves authors of those conditions. The task of capitalist ideology is to maintain the veil which keeps people from seeing that their own activities reproduce the form of their daily life; the task of critical theory is to unveil the activities of daily life, to render them transparent, to make the reproduction of the social form of capitalist activity visible within people’s daily activities.
¶Under capitalism, daily life consists of related activities which
reproduce and expand the capitalist form of social activity. The sale of
labor-time for a price (a wage), the embodiment of labor-time in
commodities (salable goods, both tangible and intangible), the
consumption of tangible and intangible commodities (such as consumer
goods and spectacles) – these activities which characterize daily life
under capitalism are not manifestations of human nature,
nor are
they imposed on men by forces beyond their control.
¶If it is held that man is by nature
an uninventive tribesman
and an inventive businessman, a submissive slave and a proud craftsman
an independent hunter and a dependent wage-worker, then either man’s
nature
is an empty concept, or man’s nature
depends on
material and historical conditions, and is in fact a response to those
conditions.
§ Alienation of Living Activity
¶In capitalist society, creative activity takes the form of commodity production, namely production of marketable goods, and the results of human activity take the form of commodities. Marketability or salability is the universal characteristic of all practical activity and all products.
¶The products of human activity which are necessary for survival have
the form of salable goods: they are only available in exchange for
money. And money is only available in exchange for commodities. If a
large number of men accept the legitimacy of these conventions, if they
accept the convention that commodities are a prerequisite for money, and
that money is a prerequisite for survival, then they find themselves
locked into a vicious circle. Since they have no commodities, their only
exit from this circle is to regard themselves, or parts of themselves,
as commodities. And this is, in fact, the peculiar solution
which
men impose on themselves in the face of specific material and historical
conditions. They do not exchange their bodies or parts of their bodies
for money. They exchange the creative content of their lives, their
practical daily activity, for money.
¶As soon as men accept money as an equivalent for life, the sale of
living activity becomes a condition for their physical and social
survival. Life is exchanged for survival. Creation and production come
to mean sold activity. A man’s activity is productive,
useful to
society, only when it is sold activity. And the man himself is a
productive member of society only if the activities of his daily life
are sold activities. As soon as people accept the terms of this
exchange, daily activity takes the form of universal prostitution.
¶The sold creative power, or sold daily activity, takes the form of
labor. Labor is a historically specific form of human activity.
Labor is abstract activity which has only one property: it is
marketable, it can be sold for a given quantity of money. Labor is
indifferent activity: indifferent to the particular task
performed and indifferent to the particular subject to which the task is
directed. Digging, printing and carving are different activities, but
all three are labor in capitalist society. Labor is simply
earning money.
Living activity which takes the form of labor is a
means to earn money. Life becomes a means of survival.
¶This ironic reversal is not the dramatic climax of an imaginative novel; it is a fact of daily life in capitalist society. Survival, namely self-preservation and reproduction, is not the means to creative practical activity, but precisely the other way around. Creative activity in the form of labor, namely sold activity, is a painful necessity for survival; labor is the means to self-preservation and reproduction.
¶The sale of living activity brings about another reversal. Through
sale, the labor of an individual becomes the property
of another,
it is appropriated by another, it comes under the control of another. In
other words, a person’s activity becomes the activity of another, the
activity of its owner; it becomes alien to the person who
performs it. Thus one’s life, the accomplishments of an
individual in the world, the difference which his life makes in the life
of humanity, are not only transformed into labor, a painful
condition for survival; they are transformed into alien
activity, activity performed by the buyer of that labor. In capitalist
society, the architects, the engineers, the laborers, are not builders;
the man who buys their labor is the builder; their projects,
calculations and motions are alien to them; their living activity, their
accomplishments, are his.
¶Academic sociologists, who take the sale of labor for granted,
understand this alienation of labor as a feeling: the worker’s activity
appears
alien to the worker, it seems
to be controlled by
another. However, any worker can explain to the academic sociologists
that the alienation is neither a feeling nor an idea in the worker’s
head, but a real fact about the worker’s daily life. The sold activity
is in fact alien to the worker; his labor is in fact
controlled by its buyer.
¶In exchange for his sold activity, the worker gets money, the
conventionally accepted means of survival in capitalist society. With
this money he can buy commodities, things, but he cannot buy back his
activity. This reveals a peculiar gap
in money as the
universal equivalent.
A person can sell commodities for money,
and he can buy the same commodities with money. He can sell his living
activity for money, but he cannot buy his living activity for money.
¶The things the worker buys with his wages are first of all consumer
goods which enable him to survive, to reproduce his labor-power so as to
be able to continue selling it; and they are spectacles, objects for
passive admiration. He consumes and admires the products of human
activity passively. He does not exist in the world as an active agent
who transforms it, but as a helpless impotent spectator; he may call
this state of powerless admiration happiness,
and since labor is
painful, he may desire to be happy,
namely inactive, all
his life (a condition similar to being born dead). The commodities, the
spectacles, consume him; he uses up living energy in passive
admiration; he is consumed by things. In this sense, the more he has,
the less he is. (An individual can surmount this death-in-life through
marginal creative activity; but the population cannot, except by
abolishing the capitalist form of practical activity, by abolishing
wage-labor and thus de-alienating creative activity.)
§ The Fetishism of Commodities
¶By alienating their activity and embodying it in commodities, in material receptacles of human labor, people reproduce themselves and create Capital.
¶From the standpoint of capitalist ideology, and particularly of
academic Economics, this statement is untrue: commodities are not the
product of labor alone
; they are produced by the primordial
factors of production,
Land, Labor and Capital, the capitalist
Holy Trinity, and the main factor
is obviously the hero of the
piece, Capital.
¶The purpose of this superficial Trinity is not analysis, since
analysis is not what these Experts are paid for. They are paid to
obfuscate, to mask the social form of practical activity under
capitalism, to veil the fact that producers reproduce themselves, their
exploiters, as well as the instruments with which they’re exploited. The
Trinity formula does not succeed in convincing. It is obvious that
land is no more of a commodity producer than water, air, or the
sun. Furthermore Capital, which is at once a name for a social
relation between workers and capitalists, for the instruments of
production owned by a capitalist, and for the money-equivalent of his
instruments and intangibles,
does not produce anything more than
the ejaculations shaped into publishable form by the academic
Economists. Even the instruments of production which are the capital of
one capitalist are primordial factors of production
only if one’s
blinders limit his view to an isolated capitalist firm, since a view of
the entire economy reveals that the capital of one capitalist is the
material receptacle of the labor alienated to another capitalist.
However, though the Trinity formula does not convince, it does
accomplish the task of obfuscation by shifting the subject of the
question: instead of asking why the activity of people under capitalism
takes the form of wage-labor, potential analysts of capitalist daily
life are transformed into academic house-Marxists who ask whether or not
labor is the only factor of production.
¶Thus Economics (and capitalist ideology in general) treats land,
money, and the products of labor, as things which have the power to
produce, to create value, to work for their owners, to transform the
world. This is what Marx called the fetishism which
characterizes people’s everyday conceptions, and which is raised to the
level of dogma by Economics. For the economist, living people are
things (factors of production
), and things live
(money works,
Capital produces
).
¶The fetish worshipper attributes the product of his own activity to
his fetish. As a result, he ceases to exert his own power (the power to
transform nature, the power to determine the form and content of his
daily life); he exerts only those powers
which he attributes to
his fetish (the power
to buy commodities). In other words, the
fetish worshipper emasculates himself and attributes virility to his
fetish.
¶But the fetish is a dead thing, not a living being; it has no
virility. The fetish is no more than a thing for which, and through
which, capitalist relations are maintained. The mysterious power of
Capital, its power
to produce, its virility, does not reside in
itself, but in the fact that people alienate their creative activity,
that they sell their labor to capitalists, that they materialize or
reify their alienated labor in commodities. In other words, people are
bought with the products of their own activity, yet they see their own
activity as the activity of Capital, and their own products as the
products of Capital. By attributing creative power to Capital and not to
their own activity, they renounce their living activity, their everyday
life, to Capital, which means that people give themselves
daily, to the personification of Capital, the capitalist.
¶By selling their labor, by alienating their activity, people daily reproduce the personifications of the dominant forms of activity under capitalism, they reproduce the wage-laborer and the capitalist. They do not merely reproduce the individuals physically, but socially as well; they reproduce individuals who are sellers of labor-power, and individuals who are owners of means of production; they reproduce the individuals as well as the specific activities, the sale as well as the ownership.
¶Every time people perform an activity they have not themselves defined and do not control, every time they pay for goods they produced with money they received in exchange for their alienated activity, every time they passively admire the products of their own activity as alien objects procured by their money, they give new life to Capital and annihilate their own lives.
¶The aim of the process is the reproduction of the relation between the worker and the capitalist. However, this is not the aim of the individual agents engaged in it. Their activities are not transparent to them; their eyes are fixed on the fetish that stands between the act and its result. The individual agents keep their eyes fixed on things, precisely those things for which capitalist relations are established. The worker as producer aims to exchange his daily labor for money-wages, he aims precisely for the thing through which his relation to the capitalist is re-established, the thing through which he reproduces himself as a wage-worker and the other as a capitalist. The worker as consumer exchanges his money for products of labor, precisely the things which the capitalist has to sell in order to realize his Capital.
¶The daily transformation of living activity into Capital is
mediated by things, it is not carried out by the
things. The fetish worshipper does not know this; for him labor and
land, instruments and money, entrepreneurs and bankers, are all
factors
and agents.
When a hunter wearing an amulet downs
a deer with a stone, he may consider the amulet an essential
factor
in downing the deer and even in providing the deer as an
object to be downed. If he is a responsible and well-educated fetish
worshipper, he will devote his attention to his amulet, nourishing it
with care and admiration; in order to improve the material conditions of
his life, he will improve the way he wears his fetish, not the way he
throws the stone; in a bind, he may even send his amulet to hunt
for him. His own daily activities are not transparent to him: when he
eats well, he fails to see that it is his own action of throwing the
stone, and not the action of the amulet, that provided his food; when he
starves, he fails to see that it is his own action of worshipping the
amulet instead of hunting, and not the wrath of his fetish, that causes
his starvation.
¶The fetishism of commodities and money, the mystification of one’s daily activities, the religion of everyday life which attributes living activity to inanimate things, is not a mental caprice born in men’s imaginations; it has its origin in the character of social relations under capitalism. Men do in fact relate to each other through things; the fetish is in fact the occasion for which they act collectively, and through which they reproduce their activity. But it is not the fetish that performs the activity. It is not Capital that transforms raw materials, nor Capital that produces goods. If living activity did not transform the materials, these would remain untransformed, inert, dead matter. If men were not disposed to continue selling their living activity, the impotence of Capital would be revealed; Capital would cease to exist; its last remaining potency would be the power to remind people of a bypassed form of everyday life characterized by daily universal prostitution.
¶The worker alienates his life in order to preserve his life. If he did not sell his living activity he could not get a wage and could not survive. However, it is not the wage that makes alienation the condition for survival. If men were collectively not disposed to sell their lives, if they were disposed to take control over their own activities, universal prostitution would not be a condition for survival. It is people’s disposition to continue selling their labor, and not the things for which they sell it, that makes the alienation of living activity necessary for the preservation of life.
¶The living activity sold by the worker is bought by the capitalist.
And it is only this living activity that breathes life into Capital and
makes it productive.
The capitalist, an owner
of raw
materials and instruments of production, presents natural objects and
products of other people’s labor as his own private property.
But
it is not the mysterious power of Capital that creates the capitalist’s
private property
; living activity is what creates the
property,
and the form of that activity is what keeps it
private.
§ Transformation of Living Activity into Capital
¶The transformation of living activity into Capital takes place through things, daily, but is not carried out by things. Things which are products of human activity seem to be active agents because activities and contacts are established for and through things, and because people’s activities are not transparent to them; they confuse the mediating object with the cause.
¶In the capitalist process of production, the worker embodies or materializes his alienated living energy in an inert object by using instruments which are embodiments of other people’s activity. (Sophisticated industrial instruments embody the intellectual and manual activity of countless generations of inventors, improvers and producers from all corners of the globe and from varied forms of society.) The instruments in themselves are inert objects; they are material embodiments of living activity, but are not themselves alive. The only active agent in the production process is the living laborer. He uses the products of other people’s labor and infuses them with life, so to speak, but the life is his own; he is not able to resurrect the individuals who stored their living activity in his instrument. The instrument may enable him to do more during a given time period, and in this sense it may raise his productivity. But only the living labor which is able to produce can be productive.
¶For example, when an industrial worker runs an electric lathe, he
uses products of the labor of generations of physicists, inventors,
electrical engineers, lathe makers. He is obviously more productive than
a craftsman who carves the same object by hand. But it is in no sense
the Capital
at the disposal of the industrial worker which is
more productive
than the Capital
of the craftsman. If
generations of intellectual and manual activity had not been embodied in
the electric lathe, if the industrial worker had to invent the lathe,
electricity, and the electric lathe, then it would take him numerous
lifetimes to turn a single object on an electric lathe, and no amount of
Capital could raise his productivity above that of the craftsman who
carves the object by hand.
¶The notion of the productivity of capital,
and particularly
the detailed measurement of that productivity,
are inventions of
the science
of Economics, that religion of capitalist daily life
which uses up people’s energy in the worship, admiration and flattery of
the central fetish of capitalist society. Medieval colleagues of these
scientists
performed detailed measurements of the height and
width of angels in Heaven, without ever asking what angels or Heaven
were, and taking for granted the existence of both.
¶The result of the worker’s sold activity is a product which does not belong to him. This product is an embodiment of his labor, a materialization of a part of his life, a receptacle which contains his living activity, but it is not his; it is as alien to him as his labor. He did not decide to make it, and when it is made he does not dispose of it. If he wants it, he has to buy it. What he has made is not simply a product with certain useful properties; for that he did not need to sell his labor to a capitalist in exchange for a wage; he need only have picked the necessary materials and the available tools, he need only have shaped the materials guided by his goals and limited by his knowledge and ability. (It is obvious that an individual can only do this marginally; men’s appropriation and use of the materials and tools available to them can only take place after the overthrow of the capitalist form of activity.)
¶What the worker produces under capitalist conditions is a product with a very specific property, the property of salability. What his alienated activity produces is a commodity.
¶Because capitalist production is commodity production, the statement
that the goal of the process is the satisfaction of human needs is
false; it is a rationalization and an apology. The satisfaction of
human needs
is not the goal of the capitalist or of the worker
engaged in production, nor is it a result of the process. The worker
sells his labor in order to get a wage; the specific content of the
labor is indifferent to him; he does not alienate his labor to a
capitalist who does not give him a wage in exchange for it, no matter
how many human needs this capitalist’s products may satisfy. The
capitalist buys labor and engages it in production in order to emerge
with commodities which can be sold. He is indifferent to the specific
properties of the product, just as he is indifferent to people’s needs;
all that interests him about the product is how much it will sell for,
and all that interests him about people’s needs is how much they
need
to buy and how they can be coerced, through propaganda and
psychological conditioning, to need
more. The capitalist’s goal
is to satisfy his need to reproduce and enlarge Capital, and
the result of the process is the expanded reproduction of wage labor and
Capital (which are not human needs
).
¶The commodity produced by the worker is exchanged by the capitalist for a specific quantity of money; the commodity is a value which is exchanged for an equivalent value. In other words, the living and past labor materialized in the product can exist in two distinct yet equivalent forms, in commodities and in money, or in what is common to both, value. This does not mean that value is labor. Value is the social form of reified (materialized) labor in capitalist society.
¶Under capitalism, social relations are not established directly; they are established through value. Everyday activity is not exchanged directly; it is exchanged in the form of value. Consequently, what happens to living activity under capitalism cannot be traced by observing the activity itself, but only by following the metamorphoses of value.
¶When the living activity of people takes the form of labor
(alienated activity), it acquires the property of exchangeability; it
acquires the form of value. In other words, the labor can be exchanged
for an equivalent
quantity of money (wages). The deliberate
alienation of living activity, which is perceived as necessary for
survival by the members of capitalist society, itself reproduces the
capitalist form within which alienation is necessary for survival.
Because of the fact that living activity has the form of value, the
products of that activity must also have the form of value: they must be
exchangeable for money. This is obvious since, if the products of labor
did not take the form of value, but for example the form of useful
objects at the disposal of society, then they would either remain in the
factory or they would be taken freely by the members of society whenever
a need for them arose; in either case, the money-wages received by the
workers would have no value, and living activity could not be
sold for an equivalent
quantity of money; living
activity could not be alienated. Consequently, as soon as living
activity takes the form of value, the products of that activity take the
form of value, and the reproduction of everyday life takes place through
changes or metamorphoses of value.
¶The capitalist sells the products of labor on a market; he exchanges them for an equivalent sum of money; he realizes a determined value. The specific magnitude of this value on a particular market is the price of the commodities. For the academic Economist, Price is St. Peter’s key to the gates of Heaven. Like Capital itself, Price moves within a wonderful world which consists entirely of objects; the objects have human relations with each other, and are alive; they transform each other, communicate with each other; they marry and have children. And of course it is only through the grace of these intelligent, powerful and creative objects that people can be so happy in capitalist society.
¶In the Economist’s pictorial representations of the workings of
heaven, the angels do everything and men do nothing at all; men simply
enjoy what these superior beings do for them. Not only does Capital
produce and money work; other mysterious beings have similar virtues.
Thus Supply, a quantity of things which are sold, and Demand, a quantity
of things which are bought, together determine Price, a quantity of
money; when Supply and Demand marry on a particular point of the
diagram, they give birth to Equilibrium Price, which corresponds to a
universal state of bliss. The activities of everyday life are played out
by things, and people are reduced to things (factors of
production
) during their productive
hours, and to passive
spectators of things during their leisure time.
The virtue of the
Economic Scientist consists of his ability to attribute the outcome of
people’s everyday activities to things, and of his inability to see the
living activity of people underneath the antics of the things. For the
Economist, the things through which the activity of people is
regulated under capitalism are themselves the mothers and sons, the
causes and consequences of their own activity.
¶The magnitude of value, namely the price of a commodity, the quantity of money for which it exchanges, is not determined by things, but by the daily activities of people. Supply and demand, perfect and imperfect competition, are nothing more than social forms of products and activities in capitalist society; they have no life of their own. The fact that activity is alienated, namely that labor-time is sold for a specific sum of money, that it has a certain value, has several consequences for the magnitude of the value of the products of that labor. The value of the sold commodities must at least be equal to the value of the labor-time. This is obvious both from the standpoint of the individual capitalist firm, and from the standpoint of society as a whole. If the value of the commodities sold by the individual capitalist were smaller than the value of the labor he hired, then his labor expenditures alone would be larger than his earnings, and he would quickly go bankrupt. Socially, if the value of the laborers production were smaller than the value of their consumption, then the labor force could not even reproduce itself, not to speak of a class of capitalists. However, if the value of the commodities were merely equal to the value of the labor-time expended on them, the commodity producers would merely reproduce themselves, and their society would not be a capitalist society; their activity might still consist of commodity production, but it would not be capitalist commodity production.
¶For labor to create Capital, the value of the products of labor must be larger than the value of the labor. In other words, the labor force must produce a surplus product, a quantity of goods which it does not consume, and this surplus product must be transformed into surplus value, a form of value which is not appropriated by workers as wages, but by capitalists as profit. Furthermore, the value of the products of labor must be larger still, since living labor is not the only kind of labor materialized in them. In the production process, workers expend their own energy, but they also use up the stored labor of others as instruments, and they shape materials on which labor was previously expended.
¶This leads to the strange result that the value of the laborer’s products and the value of his wage are different magnitudes, namely that the sum of money received by the capitalist when he sells the commodities produced by his hired laborers is different from the sum he pays the laborers. This difference is not explained by the fact that the used-up materials and tools must be paid for. If the value of the sold commodities were equal to the value of the living labor and the instruments, there would still be no room for capitalists. The fact is that the difference between the two magnitudes must be large enough to support a class of capitalists – not only the individuals, but also the specific activity that these individuals engage in, namely the purchase of labor. The difference between the total value of the products and the value of the labor spent on their production is surplus value, the seed of Capital.
¶In order to locate the origin of surplus value, it is necessary to examine why the value of the labor is smaller than the value of the commodities produced by it. The alienated activity of the worker transforms materials with the aid of instruments, and produces a certain quantity of commodities. However, when these commodities are sold and the used-up materials and instruments are paid for, the workers are not given the remaining value of their products as their wages; they are given less. In other words, during every working day, the workers perform a certain quantity of unpaid labor, forced labor, for which they receive no equivalent.
¶The performance of this unpaid labor, this forced labor, is another
condition for survival
in capitalist society. However, like
alienation, this condition is not imposed by nature, but by the
collective practice of people, by their everyday activities. Before the
existence of unions, an individual worker accepted whatever forced labor
was available, since rejection of the labor would have meant that other
workers would accept the available terms of exchange, and the individual
worker would receive no wage. Workers competed with each other for the
wages offered by capitalists; if a worker quit because the wage was
unacceptably low, an unemployed worker was willing to replace him, since
for the unemployed a small wage is higher than no wage at all. This
competition among workers was called free labor
by capitalists,
who made great sacrifices to maintain the freedom of workers, since it
was precisely this freedom that preserved the surplus value of the
capitalist and made it possible for him to accumulate Capital. It was
not any worker’s aim to produce more goods than he was paid for. His aim
was to get a wage which was as large as possible. However, the existence
of workers who got no wage at all, and whose conception of a large wage
was consequently more modest than that of an employed worker, made it
possible for the capitalist to hire labor at a lower wage. In fact, the
existence of unemployed workers made it possible for the capitalist to
pay the lowest wage that workers were willing to work for. Thus the
result of the collective daily activity of the workers, each striving
individually for the largest possible wage, was to lower the wages of
all; the effect of the competition of each against all was that all got
the smallest possible wage, and the capitalist got the largest possible
surplus.
¶The daily practice of all annuls the goals of each. But the workers did not know that their situation was a product of their own daily behavior; their own activities were not transparent to them. To the workers it seemed that low wages were simply a natural part of life, like illness and death, and that falling wages were a natural catastrophe, like a flood or a hard winter. The critiques of socialists and the analyses of Marx, as well as an increase in industrial development which afforded more time for reflection, stripped away some of the veils and made it possible for workers to see through their activities to some extent. However, in Western Europe and the United States, workers did not get rid of the capitalist form of daily life; they formed unions. And in the different material conditions of the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe, workers (and peasants) replaced the capitalist class with a state bureaucracy that purchases alienated labor and accumulates Capital in the name of Marx.
¶With unions, daily life is similar to what it was before unions. In fact, it is almost the same. Daily life continues to consist of labor, of alienated activity, and of unpaid labor, or forced labor. The unionized worker no longer settles the terms of his alienation; union functionaries do this for him. The terms on which the worker’s activity is alienated are no longer guided by the individual worker’s need to accept what is available; they are now guided by the union bureaucrat’s need to maintain his position as pimp between the sellers of labor and the buyers.
¶With or without unions, surplus value is neither a product of nature
nor of Capital; it is created by the daily activities of people. In the
performance of their daily activities, people are not only disposed to
alienate these activities, they are also disposed to reproduce the
conditions which force them to alienate their activities, to reproduce
Capital and thus the power of Capital to purchase labor. This is not
because they do not know what the alternative is.
A person who is
incapacitated by chronic indigestion because he eats too much grease
does not continue eating grease because he does not know what the
alternative is. Either he prefers being incapacitated to giving up
grease, or else it is not clear to him that his daily consumption of
grease causes his incapacity. And if his doctor, preacher, teacher and
politician tell him, first, that the grease is what keeps him alive, and
secondly that they already do for him everything he would do if he were
well, then it is not surprising that his activity is not transparent to
him and that he makes no great effort to render it transparent.
¶The production of surplus value is a condition of survival, not for
the population, but for the capitalist system. Surplus value is the
portion of the value of commodities produced by labor which is not
returned to the laborers. It can be expressed either in commodities or
in money (just as Capital can be expressed either as a quantity things
or of money), but this does not alter the fact that it is an expression
for the materialized labor which is stored in a given quantity of
products. Since the products can be exchanged for an equivalent
quantity of money, the money stands for,
or represents, the same
value as the products. The money can, in turn, be exchanged for another
quantity of products of equivalent
value. The ensemble of these
exchanges, which take place simultaneously during the performance of
capitalist daily life, constitutes the capitalist process of
circulation. It is through this process that the metamorphosis of
surplus value into Capital takes place.
¶The portion of value which does not return to labor, namely surplus value, allows the capitalist to exist, and it also allows him to do much more than simply exist. The capitalist invests a portion of this surplus value; he hires new workers and buys new means of production; he expands his dominion. What this means is that the capitalist accumulates new labor, both in the form of the living labor he hires and of the past labor (paid and unpaid) which is stored in the materials and machines he buys.
¶The capitalist class as a whole accumulates the surplus labor of society, but this process takes place on a social scale and consequently cannot be seen if one observes only the activities of an individual capitalist. It must be remembered that the products bought by a given capitalist as instruments have the same characteristics as the products he sells. A first capitalist sells instruments to a second capitalist for a given sum of value, and only a part of this value is returned to workers as wages; the remaining part is surplus value, with which the first capitalist buys new instruments and labor. The second capitalist buys the instruments for the given value, which means that he pays for the total quantity of labor rendered to the first capitalist, the quantity of labor which was remunerated as well as the quantity performed free of charge. This means that the instruments accumulated by the second capitalist contain the unpaid labor performed for the first. The second capitalist, in turn, sells his products for a given value, and returns only a portion of this value to his laborers; he uses the remainder for new instruments and labor.
¶If the whole process were squeezed into a single time period, and if all the capitalists were aggregated into one, it would he seen that the value with which the capitalist acquires new instruments and labor is equal to the value of the products which he did not return to the producers. This accumulated surplus labor is Capital.
¶In terms of capitalist society as a whole, the total Capital is equal to the sum of unpaid labor performed by generations of human beings whose lives consisted of the daily alienation of their living activity. In other words Capital, in the face of which men sell their living days, is the product of the sold activity of men, and is reproduced and expanded every day a man sells another working day, every moment he decides to continue living the capitalist form of daily life.
§ Storage and Accumulation of Human Activity
¶The transformation of surplus labor into Capital is a specific historical form of a more general process, the process of industrialization, the permanent transformation of man’s material environment.
¶Certain essential characteristics of this consequence of human
activity under capitalism can he grasped by means of a simplified
illustration. In an imaginary society, people spend most of their active
time producing food and other necessities; only part of their time is
surplus time
in the sense that it is exempted from the production
of necessities. This surplus activity may be devoted to the production
of food for priests and warriors who do not themselves produce; it may
be used to produce goods which are burned for sacred occasions; it may
be used up in the performance of ceremonies or gymnastic exercises. In
any of these cases, the material conditions of these people are not
likely to change, from one generation to another, as a result of their
daily activities. However, one generation of people of this imaginary
society may store their surplus time instead of using it up. For
example, they may spend this surplus time winding up springs. The next
generation may unwind the energy stored in the springs to perform
necessary tasks, or may simply use the energy of the springs to wind new
springs. In either case, the stored surplus labor of the earlier
generation will provide the new generation with a larger quantity of
surplus working time. The new generation may also store this surplus in
springs and in other receptacles. In a relatively short period, the
labor stored in the springs will exceed the labor time available to any
living generation; with the expenditure of relatively little energy, the
people of this imaginary society will be able to harness the springs to
most of their necessary tasks, and also to the task of winding new
springs for coming generations. Most of the living hours which they
previously spent producing necessities will now be available for
activities which are not dictated by necessity but projected by the
imagination.
¶At first glance it seems unlikely that people would devote living hours to the bizarre task of winding springs. It seems just as unlikely, even if they wound the springs, that they would store them for future generations, since the unwinding of the springs might provide, for example, a marvelous spectacle on festive days.
¶However, if people did not dispose of their own lives, if their working activity were not their own, if their practical activity consisted of forced labor, then human activity might well be harnessed to the task of winding springs, the task of storing surplus working time in material receptacles. The historical role of Capitalism, a role which was performed by people who accepted the legitimacy of others to dispose of their lives, consisted precisely of storing human activity in material receptacles by means of forced labor.
¶As soon as people submit to the power
of money to buy stored
labor as well as living activity, as soon as they accept the fictional
right
of money-holders to control and dispose of the stored as
well as the living activity of society, they transform money into
Capital and the owners of money into Capitalists.
¶This double alienation, the alienation of living activity in the form of wage labor, and the alienation of the activity of past generations in the form of stored labor (means of production), is not a single act which took place sometime in history. The relation between workers and capitalists is not a thing which imposed itself on society at some point in the past, once and for all. At no time did men sign a contract, or even make a verbal agreement, in which they gave up the power over their living activity, and in which they gave up the power over the living activity of all future generations on all parts of the globe.
¶Capital wears the mask of a natural force; it seems as solid as the earth itself; its movements appear as irreversible as tides; its crises seem as unavoidable as earthquakes and floods. Even when it is admitted that the power of Capital is created by men, this admission may merely be the occasion for the invention of an even more imposing mask, the mask of a man-made force, a Frankenstein monster, whose power inspires more awe than that of any natural force.
¶However, Capital is neither a natural force nor a man-made monster which was created sometime in the past and which dominated human life ever since.
¶The power of Capital does not reside in money, since money is a
social convention which has no more power
than men are willing to
grant it; when men refuse to sell their labor, money cannot perform even
the simplest tasks, because money does not work.
¶Nor does the power of Capital reside in the material receptacles in
which the labor of past generations is stored, since the potential
energy stored in these receptacles can be liberated by the activity of
living people whether or not the receptacles are Capital, namely alien
property.” Without living activity, the collection of objects which
constitute society’s Capital would merely be a scattered heap of
assorted artifacts with no life of their own, and the owners
of
Capital would merely be a scattered assortment of uncommonly uncreative
people (by training) who surround themselves with bits of paper in a
vain attempt to resuscitate memories of past grandeur. The only
power
of Capital resides in the daily activities of living
people; this power
consists of the disposition of people to sell
their daily activities in exchange for money, and to give up control
over the products of their own activity and of the activity of earlier
generations.
¶As soon as a person sells his labor to a capitalist and accepts only a part of his product as payment for that labor, he creates conditions for the purchase and exploitation of other people. No man would willingly give his arm or his child in exchange for money; yet when a man deliberately and consciously sells his working life in order to acquire the necessities for life, he not only reproduces the conditions which continue to make the sale of his life a necessity for its preservation; he also creates conditions which make the sale of life a necessity for other people. Later generations may of course refuse to sell their working lives for the same reason that he refused to sell his arm; however each failure to refuse alienated and forced labor enlarges the stock of stored labor with which Capital can buy working lives.
¶In order to transform surplus labor into Capital, the capitalist has to find a way to store it in material receptacles, in new means of production, and he must hire new laborers to activate the new means of production. In other words, he must enlarge his enterprise, or start a new enterprise in a different branch of production. This presupposes or requires the existence of materials that can be shaped into new salable commodities, the existence of buyers of the new products, and the existence of people who are poor enough to be willing to sell their labor. These requirements are themselves created by capitalist activity, and capitalists recognize no limits or obstacles to their activity; the democracy of Capital demands absolute freedom.
¶Imperialism is not merely the last stage
of Capitalism; it is
also the first.
¶Anything which can be transformed into a marketable good is grist for Capital’s mill, whether it lies on the capitalist’s land or on the neighbor’s, whether it lies above ground or under, floats on the sea or crawls on its floor; whether it is confined to other continents or other planets. All of humanity’s explorations of nature, from Alchemy to Physics, are mobilized to search for new materials in which to store labor, to find new objects that someone can be taught to buy.
¶Buyers for old and new products are created by any and all available
means, and new means are constantly discovered. Open markets
and
open doors
are established by force and fraud. If people lack the
means to buy the capitalists’ products, they are hired by capitalists
and are paid for producing the goods they wish to buy; if local
craftsmen already produce what the capitalists have to sell, the
craftsmen are ruined or bought-out; if laws or traditions ban the use of
certain products, the laws and the traditions are destroyed; if people
lack the objects on which to use the capitalists’ products, they are
taught to buy these objects; if people run out of physical or biological
wants, then capitalists satisfy
their spiritual wants
and
hire psychologists to create them; if people are so satiated with the
products of capitalists that they can no longer use new objects, they
are taught to buy objects and spectacles which have no use but can
simply be observed and admired.
¶Poor people are found in pre-agrarian and agrarian societies on every
continent; if they are not poor enough to be willing to sell their labor
when the capitalists arrive, they are impoverished by the activities of
the capitalists themselves. The lands of hunters gradually become the
private property
of owners
who use state violence to
restrict the hunters to reservations
which do not contain enough
food to keep them alive. The tools of peasants gradually become
available only from the same merchant who generously lends them the
money with which to buy the tools, until the peasants’ debts
are
so large that they are forced to sell land which neither they nor any of
their ancestors had ever bought. The buyers of craftsmen’s products
gradually become reduced to the merchants who market the products, until
the day comes when a merchant decides to house his craftsmen
under the same roof, and provides them with the instruments which will
enable all of them to concentrate their activity on the production of
the most profitable items. Independent as well as dependent hunters,
peasants and craftsmen, free men as well as slaves, are transformed into
hired laborers. Those who previously disposed of their own lives in the
face of harsh material conditions cease to dispose of their own lives
precisely when they take up the task of modifying their material
conditions; those who were previously conscious creators of their own
meager existence become unconscious victims of their own activity even
while abolishing the meagerness of their existence. Men who were much
but had little now have much but are little.
¶The production of new commodities, the opening
of new markets,
the creation of new workers, are not three separate activities; they are
three aspects of the same activity. A new labor force is created
precisely in order to produce the new commodities; the wages received by
these laborers are themselves the new market; their unpaid labor is the
source of new expansion. Neither natural nor cultural barriers halt the
spread of Capital, the transformation of people’s daily activity into
alienated labor, the transformation of their surplus labor into the
private property
of capitalists. However, Capital is not a
natural force; it is a set of activities performed by people every day;
it is a form of daily life; its continued existence and expansion
presuppose only one essential condition: the disposition of people to
continue to alienate their working lives and thus reproduce the
capitalist form of daily life.